Philosophy:Ousia

From HandWiki
Revision as of 06:44, 5 February 2024 by Importwiki (talk | contribs) (add)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Short description: Term in ancient Greek philosophy and Christian theology


Ousia (/ˈziə, ˈsiə, ˈʒə, ˈʃə/; Ancient Greek:) is a philosophical and theological term, originally used in ancient Greek philosophy, then later in Christian theology. It was used by various ancient Greek philosophers, like Plato and Aristotle, as a primary designation for philosophical concepts of essence or substance. In contemporary philosophy, it is analogous to English concepts of being and ontic. In Christian theology, the concept of θεία ουσία (divine essence) is one of the most important doctrinal concepts, central to the development of trinitarian doctrine.[1]

The Ancient Greek term θεία ουσία (theia ousia; divine essence) was translated in Latin as essentia or substantia, and hence in English as essence or substance.[2]

Etymology

The term οὐσία is an Ancient Greek noun, formed on the feminine present participle of the verb εἰμί, eimí, meaning "to be, I am", so similar grammatically to the English noun "being". There was no equivalent grammatical formation in Latin, and it was translated as essentia or substantia. Cicero coined essentia[3] and the philosopher Seneca and rhetorician Quintilian used it as equivalent for οὐσία, while Apuleius rendered οὐσία both as essentia or substantia. In order to designate οὐσία, early Christian theologian Tertullian favored the use of substantia over essentia, while Augustine of Hippo and Boethius took the opposite stance, preferring the use of essentia as designation for οὐσία.[4][5] Some of the most prominent Latin authors, like Hilary of Poitiers, noted that those variants were often being used with different meanings.[6] Some modern authors also suggest that the Ancient Greek term οὐσία is properly translated as essentia (essence), while substantia has a wider spectrum of meanings.[7]

From οὐσία (essence), philosophical and theological term οὐσιότης (essentiality) was also derived. It was used by Platonists, like Alcinous, as designation for one of the basic properties of divinity or godhead.[8]

Philosophy

Aristotle defined πρῶται οὐσίαι (protai ousiai; primary essences) in the Categories as that which is neither said of nor in any subject, e.g., "this human" in particular, or "this ox". The genera in biology and other natural kinds are substances in a secondary sense, as universals, formally defined by the essential qualities of the primary substances; i.e., the individual members of those kinds.[9]

In Book IV of Metaphysics Aristotle explores the nature and attributes of being (ousia). Aristotle divides the things that there are, or "beings," into categories. Aristotle calls these substances and argues that there are many senses in which a thing may be said "to be" but it is related to one central point and is ambiguous.[10]

Aristotle states that there are both primary and secondary substances. In Categories Aristotle argues that primary substances are ontologically based and if the primary substances did not exist then it would be impossible for other things to exist.[11] The other things are regarded as the secondary substances (also known as accidents). Secondary substances are thus ontologically dependent on substances.[11]

In Metaphysics, Aristotle states that everything which is healthy is related to health (primary substance) as in one sense because it preserves health and in the other because it is capable of it. Without the primary substance (health) we would not be able to have the secondary substances (anything related to health). While all the secondary substances are deemed "to be" it is in relation to the primary substance.[10]

The question, what is being, is seeking an answer to something "that is." A contemporary example in rhetoric would be to look at a color. Using white as an example, when we define a color, we define it by association. Snow is white. Paper is white. A cow is white. But what is white? While we are saying things that are white, we are not defining what white is without qualification. Ousia is thus the answer to the question of "what is being" when the question is without qualification. The unqualified answer of what is white is the ousia of white.

Much later, Martin Heidegger said that the original meaning of the word ousia was lost in its translation to the Latin, and, subsequently, in its translation to modern languages. For him, ousia means Being, not substance, that is, not some thing or some being that "stood" (-stance) "under" (sub-). Moreover, he also used the binomial parousia–apousia, denoting presence–absence,[clarification needed] and hypostasis denoting existence.[12]

In the 20th century, the Australian philosopher Colin Murray Turbayne put forth the argument that the concept of "material substance" or "substance" conveys little if any meaning at best.[13] In his view, this Aristotelean construct is more properly characterized as a linguistic metaphor which has been unintentionally interpreted as literal truth through the use of deductive reasoning within the context of the mechanistic ontological models of the universe first described by Isaac Newton and Rene Descartes.[14] In the process, modern man has unknowingly fallen victim to a mind-body dualism which underlies much of the philosophical materialism which prevails within the modern world.[15][16]

Christian theology

Lua error: not enough memory. The concept of Lua error: not enough memory. (Lua error: not enough memory.; divine essence) is one of the most important concepts in Christian theology. It was developed gradually by Early Church Fathers during the first centuries of Christian History. Central debates over the doctrinal use and meaning of οὐσία were held during the 4th century, and also continued later, some of them lasting up to the present day.Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1.Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1.

New Testament

The word Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1. is used in the New Testament only in relation to the substance in the sense of goods, twice in the parable of the Prodigal Son where the son asked his father to divide to him his inheritance, and then wasted it on riotous living.[17][18]

An apparently related word, Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1. (affixing the prefix epi- to the word), is used in the Lord's Prayer, but nowhere else in the scriptures. Elsewhere, it was believed to be present in one papyrus (a list of expenses) among expenses for chick-peas, straw, etc., and for material.[19] In 1998, according to a xerographic copy of a papyrus found in the Yale Papyrus Collection (from the Beinecke Rare Book and Manuscript Library) inventory 19 (a.k.a. P.C.+YBR inv 19), it was suggested that the document had been transcribed differently from other early manuscripts and that the actual word used in that particular papyrus was elaiou, meaning "oil".[20]

Early Christianity

Origen (d. 251) used ousia in defining God as one genus of ousia, while being three, distinct species of hypostasis: the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit. The Synods of Antioch condemned the word homoousios (same essence) because it originated in pagan Greek philosophy.Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1. John Chapman's Catholic Encyclopedia entry for Paul of Samosata states:

It must be regarded as certain that the council, which condemned Paul, rejected the term homoousios; but, naturally, only in a false sense, used by Paul; not, it seems, because he meant by it a unity of Hypostasis in the Trinity (so St. Hilary), but because he intended, by it, a common essence, out of which both Father and Son proceeded, or which it divided between them – so St. Basil and St. Athanasius; but the question is not clear. The objectors to the Nicene doctrine in the fourth century made copious use of this disapproval of the Nicene word by a famous council.[21]

In 325, the First Council of Nicaea condemned Arianism and formulated a creed, which stated that in the Godhead the Son was Homoousios (same in essence) of the Father. However, controversy did not stop and many Eastern clerics rejected the term because of its earlier condemnation in the usage of Paul of Samosata. Subsequent Emperors Constantius II (reigned 337–361) and Valens (reigned 364–378) supported Arianism and theologians came up with alternative wordings like Homoios (similar), homoiousios (similar in essence), or Anomoios (unsimilar). While the Homoios achieved the support of several councils and the Emperors, those of an opposing view were suppressed. The adherents of the Homoiousios eventually joined forces with the (mostly Western) adherents of the Homoousios and accepted the formulation of the Nicene creed.

The generally agreed-upon meaning of ousia in Eastern Christianity is "all that subsists by itself and which has not its being in another" – in contrast to hypostasis, which is used to mean "reality" or "existence".Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1.Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1. John Damascene gives the following definition of the conceptual value of the two terms in his Dialectic: Ousia is a thing that exists by itself, and which has need of nothing else for its consistency. Again, ousia is all that subsists by itself and which has not its being in another.Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1.Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1.

See also

References

  1. Athanasopoulos & Schneider 2013.
  2. Aquina, Thomas (2003). "Book One" (in en). Commentary on Aristotle's Physics. A&C Black. p. 29. ISBN 978-1843715450. https://books.google.com/books?id=6CD0IRPg4roC&pg=PA29. 
  3. Conte, G.B.: "Latin Literature: a history" (1987) p. 199
  4. Owens 1951, pp. 137–154.
  5. Brown 1996, p. 276.
  6. Weedman 2007.
  7. Pásztori-Kupán 2006, pp. 59–60.
  8. Bracht 2009, p. 111.
  9. Cohen, S. Marc (2004). "Lecture on Categories". http://faculty.washington.edu/smcohen/433/catlec.htm. "Primary substances are fundamental in that "if they did not exist it would be impossible for any of the other things to exist." [Categories, 2b5]" 
  10. 10.0 10.1 Aristotle. "Metaphysics". http://arpast.org/newsevents/articles/article47.pdf. 
  11. 11.0 11.1 Cohen, Mark. "Substances". https://faculty.washington.edu/smcohen/Substances.pdf. 
  12. Heidegger 1996.
  13. Murphy, Jeffrie "G. Berkeley and the Metaphor of Mental Substance." Ratio 7 (1965):171, note 3.
  14. Shook, John R. (2005-05-15) (in en). Dictionary Of Modern American Philosophers. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-84714-470-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=DsKvAwAAQBAJ&dq=Colin+Murray+Turbayne&pg=PA2451. 
  15. Hesse, Mary (1966). "Review of The Myth of Metaphor". Foundations of Language 2 (3): 282–284. 
  16. "Berkeley Essay Prize Competition" (in en-US). https://www.sas.rochester.edu/phl/about/prize.html. 
  17. Thomas Mozley The creed or a philosophy 1893 p. 303 "III 'Ousia' In The New Testament The only appearance of this word in the New Testament is in two successive verses of the Parable of the Prodigal Son. It there designates first the 'living' which the Prodigal Son compelled his father..."
  18. "G3776 – ousia – Strong's Greek Lexicon (kjv)". https://www.blueletterbible.org/kjv/gen/1/1/s_1001. 
  19. Kittel, G., Bromiley, G. W., & Friedrich, G. (Eds.). Theological dictionary of the New Testament (electronic ed., Vol. 2, pp. 590–591). Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.
  20. Discussion on the B-Greek mailing list. 2005
  21. John Chapman. "Catholic Encyclopedia: Paul of Samosata". https://www.newadvent.org/cathen/11589a.htm. 

Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1.

Bibliography

External links

Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1.


Lua error: Internal error: The interpreter exited with status 1.