Astronomy:Anthropic Bias

From HandWiki
Revision as of 07:04, 6 February 2024 by Nautica (talk | contribs) (add)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Short description: 2002 book by Nick Bostrom
Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy
Anthropic Bias (book).jpg
AuthorNick Bostrom
LanguageEnglish
SubjectAnthropic principle
PublisherRoutledge
Publication date
2002
Media typePrint
Pages240
ISBNISBN:978-0415883948
Followed byHuman Enhancement 

Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy (2002) is a book by philosopher Nick Bostrom. Bostrom investigates how to reason when one suspects that evidence is biased by "observation selection effects", in other words, when the evidence presented has been pre-filtered by the condition that there was some appropriately positioned observer to "receive" the evidence. This conundrum is sometimes called the "anthropic principle," "self-locating belief," or "indexical information".[1][2]

Self-sampling assumption

The self-sampling assumption (SSA), one of the two major schools of anthropic probability[2] — the other being the self-indication assumption (SIA) — states that:

All other things equal, an observer should reason as if they are randomly selected from the set of all actually existent observers (past, present and future) in their reference class.

For instance, if there is a coin flip that on heads will create one observer, while on tails it will create two, then we have two possible worlds, the first with one observer, the second with two. These worlds are equally probable, hence the SSA probability of being the first (and only) observer in the heads world is ​1 2, that of being the first observer in the tails world is ​1 2 × ​1 2 = ​1 4, and the probability of being the second observer in the tails world is also ​1 4.

This is why SSA gives an answer of ​1 2 probability of heads in the Sleeping Beauty problem.

Unlike SIA, SSA is dependent on the choice of reference class. If the agents in the above example were in the same reference class as a trillion other observers, then the probability of being in the heads world, upon the agent being told they are in the sleeping beauty problem, is ≈ ​1 3, similar to SIA.

SSA may imply the doomsday argument depending on the choice of reference class. It is often used in anthropic reasoning.

Bostrom, in his book Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy, has suggested refining SSA to what he calls the strong self-sampling assumption (SSSA), which replaces "observers" in the SSA definition by "observer-moments". This coincides with the intuition that an observer who lives longer has more opportunities to experience herself existing, and it provides flexibility to refine reference classes in certain thought experiments in order to avoid paradoxical conclusions.[2]

Self-indication assumption

The self-indication assumption (SIA)[note 1] is a philosophical principle defined by Nick Bostrom in his book Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy. It states that:

All other things equal, an observer should reason as if they are randomly selected from the set of all possible observers.

Note that "randomly selected" is weighted by the probability of the observers existing: under SIA you are still unlikely to be an unlikely observer, unless there are a lot of them. It is one of the two major schools of anthropic probability, the other being the Self-Sampling Assumption (SSA).

For instance, if there is a coin flip that on heads will create one observer, while on tails it will create two, then we have three possible observers (1st observer on heads, 1st on tails, 2nd on tails). Each of these observers have an equal probability for existence, so SIA assigns ​1 3 probability to each. Alternatively, this could be interpreted as saying there are two possible observers (1st observer on either heads or tails, 2nd observer on tails), the first existing with probability one and the second existing with probability ​1 2, so SIA assigns ​2 3 to being the first observer and ​1 3 to being the second - which is the same as the first interpretation.

This is why SIA gives an answer of ​1 3 probability of heads in the Sleeping Beauty Problem.

Notice that unlike SSA, SIA is not dependent on the choice of reference class, as long as the reference class is large enough to contain all subjectively indistinguishable observers. If the reference class is large, SIA will make it more likely, but this is compensated by the much reduced probability that the agent will be that particular agent in the larger reference class.

Although this anthropic principle was originally designed as a rebuttal to the doomsday argument (by Dennis Dieks in 1992) it has general applications in the philosophy of anthropic reasoning, and Ken Olum has suggested it is important to the analysis of quantum cosmology.

Ken Olum has written in defense of the SIA.[3] Nick Bostrom and Milan Ćirković have critiqued this defense.[4]

Reviews

A review from Virginia Commonwealth University said the book "deserves a place on the shelf" of those interested in these subjects.[5]

See also

Notes

  1. Nick Bostrom originally used the term SIA in a slightly different way. What is here referred to as SIA, he referred to as the combined SSA+SIA

References

  1. "Anthropic Bias | anthropic-principle.com". http://www.anthropic-principle.com/?q=anthropic_bias. Retrieved 2015-11-03. 
  2. 2.0 2.1 2.2 Nick Bostrom, Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy (New York: Routledge, 2002).
  3. Olum, Ken (2002). "The Doomsday Argument and the Number of Possible Observers". Philosophical Quarterly 52 (207): 164–184. doi:10.1111/1467-9213.00260. 
  4. Nick Bostrom; Milan Cirkovic (2003). "The doomsday argument and the self-indication assumption: reply to Olum". Philosophical Quarterly 53 (210): 83–91. doi:10.1111/1467-9213.00298. http://www.anthropic-principle.com/preprints/olum/sia.pdf. 
  5. Manson, Neil (2003-02-09). "Anthropic Bias: Observation Selection Effects in Science and Philosophy". University of Notre Dame. https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/23266-anthropic-bias-observation-selection-effects-in-science-and-philosophy/. 

External links