Biography:Richard Gaskin

From HandWiki
Revision as of 07:51, 7 February 2024 by Nautica (talk | contribs) (fix)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Short description: British philosopher (born 1960)


Richard Gaskin
Born
Richard Maxwell Gaskin

(1960-05-08) 8 May 1960 (age 64)
Glasgow, Scotland, United Kingdom
NationalityBritish
Academic background
Alma materUniversity College, Oxford
ThesisExperience, Agency, and the Self (1988)
Doctoral advisorMichael Dummett
Other academic advisorsJohn McDowell
Influences
Academic work
DisciplinePhilosophy
Sub-discipline
School or traditionAnalytic philosophy
Institutions

Richard Maxwell Gaskin (born 8 May 1960) is a British philosopher who is a professor at the University of Liverpool. He has published on metaphysics, philosophy of language and logic, and history of philosophy, as well as on philosophy of literature, literary theory, and the European literary tradition. Gaskin received his Bachelor of Arts, Bachelor of Philosophy, and Doctor of Philosophy degrees in classics and philosophy at University College, Oxford, and has held academic posts at St Edmund Hall, Oxford, as well as at the University of Sussex.[1]

Gaskin is the author of many published articles and nine books, including: Language and World: A Defence of Linguistic Idealism (2020), Tragedy and Redress in Western Literature: a Philosophical Perspective (2018), Language, Truth, and Literature: a Defence of Literary Humanism (2013), The Unity of the Proposition (2008), Experience and the World's Own Language: a Critique of John McDowell's Empiricism (2006), and The Sea Battle and the Master Argument: Aristotle and Diodorus Cronus on the metaphysics of the future (1995).[2]

Early life, education, and career

Gaskin was born in 1960 in Milngavie, Glasgow, and attended Robert Gordon's College, Aberdeen, where his father, Maxwell Gaskin, held the Jaffrey Chair of Political Economy.[3] He studied literae humaniores (classics and philosophy) at University College, Oxford, and obtained his BA (first class) in 1982. While an undergraduate at Oxford he was secretary of the Oxford University Dramatic Society from 1981 to 82, and directed a production of Marlowe's Dr Faustus at the Oxford Playhouse in March 1981.[4] He took the BPhil exam in 1986, supervised by John McDowell. In 1987 he won the Gaisford Dissertation Prize in classical literature for his essay Tragedy and Subjectivity in Virgil’s 'Aeneid' .[5] He was awarded the DPhil in 1988 for a thesis supervised by Michael Dummett, David Wiggins, and Barry Stroud, entitled Experience, Agency, and the Self.[6] From 1988 to 1989 Gaskin spent a year as an Alexander von Humboldt visiting fellow at the University of Mainz, Germany, researching decision-making in classical literature under the Virgilian scholar Antonie Wlosok.[7] From 1991 to 2001, he was a Lecturer (from 1997 Reader) in Philosophy at the University of Sussex.[8] In 2001 he became Professor in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Liverpool.[9]

Philosophical work

A central part of Gaskin's work focuses on the doctrine of linguistic idealism, the idea that the world is produced by, and depends on, language. Gaskin argues that the dependence of the world on language is a logical and constitutive one, rather than a temporal one: objects (such as tables and chairs) exist in virtue of, and are constituted as objects by, the existence of sentences about them; language 'makes the world', but not in the sense that there was a time at which it pre-existed the world. Although human language is a purely contingent product of evolution, there is a transcendental sense in which the existence of the world depends on the existence of language—more precisely, on the capacity of language to talk about the world. In Gaskin's view the world is constitutively composed of propositions, which are referents of sentences; these propositions contain the ordinary objects of our discourse. In Language and World (2020), Gaskin develops the theory of linguistic idealism and defends it against several objections. He addresses the problem that some mathematical entities, in particular uncomputable sets of real numbers, cannot be distinguished by language; he does this by developing a ‘split-level' version of linguistic idealism. In his approach all the basic entities of the world can be named in language, and all further entities, even if they cannot be named, can be derived from these basic entities by describable constructive operations. In Tragedy and Redress in Western Literature: A Philosophical Perspective (2018), Gaskin argues that not even the tragic aspects of life (such as pain and suffering) are beyond language, an objection commonly raised against the idea that language is omnicompetent to talk about and describe reality.

In his writings on literature, Gaskin has defended a version of literary humanism, according to which works of imaginative literature have an objective meaning which is fixed at the time of their production and is the same for all readers.[10] In addition to his publications in philosophy of literature, he has written a study of the poets Horace and Housman,[11] essays on Virgil (e.g. On being pessimistic about the end of the 'Aeneid'[12]), Homer (e.g. Do Homeric Heroes make real decisions?[13]), the classicist Richard Bentley,[14] and the essayist Charles Lamb.[15] Gaskin has translated selections from Apollonius of Rhodes's Greek poem Argonautica into English verse.[16] Gaskin has written on ancient and on medieval philosophy,[17][18] and on Wittgenstein.[19] He maintains a website on which he mounts recordings of English, German, and Latin poetry.[20]

Publications[2][21]

Selected books

Othello and the Problem of Knowledge: Reading Shakespeare through Wittgenstein (Routledge 2023)

Language and world: a Defence of Linguistic Idealism (Routledge 2020).

Tragedy and Redress in Western Literature: a Philosophical Perspective (Routledge 2018).

Horace and Housman (Palgrave Macmillan 2013).

Language, Truth, and Literature: a Defence of Literary Humanism (OUP 2013).

The Unity of the Proposition (OUP 2008).

Experience and the World's Own Language: a Critique of John McDowell's Empiricism (Clarendon Press 2006).

The Sea Battle and the Master Argument: Aristotle and Diodorus Cronus on the Metaphysics of the Future (Walter de Gruyter 1995).

Selected articles

On being pessimistic about the end of the Aeneid, forthcoming in Harvard Studies in Classical Philology.[22]

A Defence of the Resemblance Meaning of “What it’s like”, Mind 128, 2019, 673–98. DOI 10.1093/mind/fzx023.

From the unity of the proposition to linguistic idealism, Synthese 196, 2019, 1325–42. DOI 10.1007/s11229-016-1081-5.

Identity and Reference in a Black Universe, in P. Stalmaszczyk ed., Philosophical and Linguistic Analyses of Reference (Frankfurt: Lang, 2016), 19–41. DOI 10.3726/978-3-653-05429-3.

The Identity Theory of Truth, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, published May 1, 2015.

Meaning, Normativity, and Naturalism, in B. Dainton and H. Robinson eds., The Bloomsbury Companion to Analytic Philosophy (London: Bloomsbury, 2013), 230–54. ISBN:978-1-474-23648-5.

When Logical Atomism met the Theaetetus: Ryle on Naming and Saying, in M. Beaney ed., The Oxford Handbook of the History of Analytic Philosophy (Oxford: OUP, 2013), 851–69. DOI 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199238842.013.0037.

Reach's Puzzle and Mention (co-authored with Daniel J. Hill), Dialectica 67, 2013, 201–22. DOI 10.1111/1746-8361.12021.

On Neutral Relations (co-authored with Daniel J. Hill), Dialectica 66, 2012, 167–86. DOI 10.1111/j.1746-8361.2012.01294.x.

Bentley's classicism, Paradise Lost, and the Schema Horatianum, International Journal of the Classical Tradition 17, 2010, 354–65. DOI [1].

Realism and the Picture Theory of Meaning, Philosophical Topics 37, 2009, 49–62. DOI 10.5840/philtopics200937115.

John Wyclif and the Theory of Complexly Signifiables, Vivarium 47, 2009, 74–96. DOI 10.1163/156853408X345927.

Complexe Significabilia and Aristotle's Categories, in J. Biard und I. Rosier-Catach eds., La Tradition Médiévale des Catégories (Louvain: Peeters, 2003), 187–205. ISBN:90-429-1335-5.

Nonsense and Necessity in Wittgenstein's Mature Philosophy, in R. Gaskin ed., Grammar in Early Twentieth-Century Philosophy (London: Routledge, 2001), 199–217. ISBN:978-0-415-40845-5.

Ockham's Mental Language, Connotation, and the Inherence Regress, in D. Perler ed., Ancient and Medieval Theories of Intentionality (Leiden: Brill, 2001), 227–63. ISBN:978-9-004-12295-6.

Do Homeric Heroes make Real Decisions? (revised version of 1990 CQ paper), in D. Cairns ed., Oxford Readings on Homer's Iliad (Oxford: Clarendon, 2001), 147–65. ISBN:978-0-198-72182-6.

Fatalism, Middle Knowledge, and Comparative Similarity of Worlds, Religious Studies 34, 1998, 189–203. DOI 10.1017/S0034412598004338.

Simplicius on the Meaning of Sentences: a Commentary on In Cat. 396,30–397,28, Phronesis 43, 1998, 42–62. DOI 10.1163/15685289860517793.

Peter Damian on Divine Power and the Contingency of the Past, British Journal of the History of Philosophy 5, 1997, 229–47. DOI 10.1080/09608789708570965.

Russell and Richard Brinkley on the Unity of the Proposition, History and Philosophy of Logic 18, 1997, 139–50. DOI 10.1080/01445349708837284.

Peter of Ailly and other Fourteenth-Century Thinkers on Divine Power and the Necessity of the Past, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79, 1997, 273–91. DOI 10.1515/agph.1997.79.3.273.

The Stoics on Cases, Predicates and the Unity of the Proposition, in Aristotle and After ed. R. Sorabji (London: Institute of Classical Studies, 1997), 91–108. DOI 10.1111/j.2041-5370.1997.tb02264.x.

Fregean Sense and Russellian Propositions, Philosophical Studies 86, 1997, 131–54. DOI 10.1023/A:1017929320501

Conditionals of Freedom and Middle Knowledge Philosophical Quarterly 43, 1993, 412–30. (Winner of 1992 PQ essay competition.) DOI 10.2307/2219983. Reprinted with corrections in E. Dekker et al. eds., Middle Knowledge (Peter Lang, 2000), 137–56, ISBN:978-3-631-36288-4.

Turnus, Mezentius, and the Complexity of Virgil's Aeneid, Latomus, Studies in Latin Literature and Roman History VI, 1992, 295–316, ISBN:978-2-870-31157-8.

Do Homeric Heroes make Real Decisions?, Classical Quarterly 40, 1990, 1–15. DOI 10.1017/S0009838800026768.

Can Aesthetic Value Be Explained?, British Journal of Aesthetics 29, 1989, 329–40. DOI 10.1093/bjaesthetics/29.4.329.

References

  1. The Sea Battle and the Master Argument: Aristotle and Diodorus Cronus on the Metaphysics of the Future (Berlin/ New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1995), page VII
  2. 2.0 2.1 "Richard Gaskin at Google Books". https://www.google.co.uk/search?tbo=p&tbm=bks&q=inauthor:%22Richard+Gaskin%22. 
  3. "Obituary of Professor Maxwell Gaskin". https://www.thetimes.co.uk/article/professor-maxwell-gaskin-3ckkr0779mz. 
  4. "Stage". https://warwick.ac.uk/fac/arts/ren/researchcurrent/elizabethan_jacobean_drama/christopher_marlowe/dr_faustus/stage/. 
  5. "St Edmund Hall Magazine 1986–87". https://issuu.com/stedmundhall/docs/st_edmund_hall_magazine_1986-87. 
  6. Gaskin, Richard M. (Richard Maxwell) (24 April 1988). Experience, agency and the self (Thesis). University of Oxford – via ora.ox.ac.uk.
  7. Gaskin, Richard (May 1990). "Blurb to 'Do Homeric Heroes Make Real Decisions?'". The Classical Quarterly 40 (1): 1–15. doi:10.1017/S0009838800026768. https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/classical-quarterly/article/do-homeric-heroes-make-real-decisions/A8500FB841E76C2A061A05FA3419C34D. 
  8. Gaskin, Richard (18 April 2013). Blurb to Language, Truth, and Literature. ISBN 9780199657902. https://books.google.com/books?id=dR1K8lT1_LsC. 
  9. "Richard Gaskin – University of Liverpool". https://www.liverpool.ac.uk/philosophy/staff/richard-gaskin/. 
  10. "Review of Gaskin's Language, Truth, and Literature". https://www.researchgate.net/publication/270778070. 
  11. Horace and Housman (New York, 2013). https://www.academia.edu/17534837. 
  12. Gaskin, Richard (January 2021). "On being pessimistic about the end of the Aeneid". Harvard Studies in Classical Philology. https://www.academia.edu/34387377. 
  13. Gaskin, Richard (1990). "Do Homeric Heroes make Real Decisions?". The Classical Quarterly 40 (1): 1–15. doi:10.1017/S0009838800026768. https://www.academia.edu/12706821. 
  14. Gaskin, Richard. Bentley's classicism, Paradise Lost, and the Schema Horatianum. https://www.academia.edu/12691844. 
  15. Gaskin, Richard (January 2013). "Lamb and Horace". Charles Lamb Bulletin. https://www.academia.edu/12691085. 
  16. Apollonius of Rhodes: the voyage of Argo : passages from the first three books translated into English verse, with a brief linking narrative. Leerie Books. 3 May 1995. OCLC 35137372. 
  17. Gaskin, Richard (2009). "John Wyclif and the Theory of Complexly Signifiables". Vivarium 47 (1): 74–96. doi:10.1163/156853408X345927. https://www.academia.edu/12706155. 
  18. The Sea Battle and the Master Argument: Aristotle and Diodorus Cronus on the Metaphysics of the Future (De Gruyter 1995). https://www.academia.edu/17534671. 
  19. Gaskin, Richard. Nonsense and necessity in Wittgenstein's mature philosophy. https://www.academia.edu/29450457. 
  20. "The Literary Voice". https://literaryvoice.org/. 
  21. "Richard Gaskin – University of Liverpool". https://www.liverpool.ac.uk/philosophy/staff/richard-gaskin/publications/. 
  22. Gaskin, Richard (January 2021). "On being pessimistic about the end of the Aeneid (Final version)". Harvard Studies in Classical Philology. https://www.academia.edu/34387377. 

External links