Sortition

From HandWiki
Short description: Selection of decision-makers by random sample

In governance, sortition (also known as selection by lottery, selection by lot, allotment, demarchy, stochocracy, aleatoric democracy, democratic lottery, and lottocracy) is the selection of public officials or jurors using a random representative sample.[1][2][3] This minimizes factionalism, since those selected to serve can prioritize deliberating on the policy decisions in front of them instead of campaigning.[4] In ancient Athenian democracy, sortition was the traditional and primary method for appointing political officials, and its use was regarded as a principal characteristic of democracy.[5][6] Sortition is often classified as a method for both direct democracy and deliberative democracy.

Today, sortition is commonly used to select prospective jurors in common-law systems. What has changed in recent years is the increased number of citizen groups with political advisory power,[7][8] along with calls for making sortition more consequential than elections, as it was in Athens, Venice and Florence.[9][10][11][12]

History

Ancient Athens

Athenian democracy developed in the 6th century BC out of what was then called isonomia (equality of law and political rights). Sortition was then the principal way of achieving this fairness. It was utilized to pick most[13] of the magistrates for their governing committees, and for their juries (typically of 501 men).

A kleroterion in the Ancient Agora Museum (Athens)

Most Athenians believed sortition, not elections, to be democratic[13] and used complex procedures with purpose-built allotment machines (kleroteria) to avoid the corrupt practices used by oligarchs to buy their way into office. According to the author Mogens Herman Hansen, the citizen's court was superior to the assembly because the allotted members swore an oath which ordinary citizens in the assembly did not, therefore the court could annul the decisions of the assembly. Most Greek writers who mention democracy (including Aristotle,[13][14][15] Plato,[16] Herodotus,[17] and Pericles[18]) emphasize the role of selection by lot, or state outright that being allotted is more democratic than elections (which were seen as oligarchic). Socrates[19] and Isocrates[20] however questioned whether randomly-selected decision-makers had enough expertise.

Past scholarship maintained that sortition had roots in the use of chance to divine the will of the gods, but this view is no longer common among scholars.[21] In Ancient Greek mythology, Zeus, Poseidon, and Hades used sortition to determine who ruled over which domain. Zeus got the sky, Poseidon the sea, and Hades the underworld.[22]

In Athenian democracy, to be eligible to be chosen by lot, citizens self-selected themselves into the available pool, then lotteries in the kleroteria machines. The magistracies assigned by lot generally had terms of service of one year. A citizen could not hold any particular magistracy more than once in his lifetime, but could hold other magistracies. All male citizens over 30 years of age, who were not disenfranchised by atimia, were eligible. Those selected through lot underwent examination called dokimasia to ensure citizenship and consider life, character, and at times, property; capacity for a post was assumed. Rarely were selected citizens discarded.[23] Magistrates, once in place, were subjected to constant monitoring by the Assembly. Magistrates appointed by lot had to render account of their time in office upon their leave, called euthynai. However, any citizen could request the suspension of a magistrate with due reason.[24]

A Kleroterion was used to select eligible and willing citizens to serve jury duty. This bolstered the initial Athenian system of democracy by getting new and different jury members from each tribe to avoid corruption.[25] James Wycliffe Headlam explains that the Athenian Council (500 administrators randomly selected), would commit occasional mistakes such as levying taxes that were too high. Headlam found minor instances of corruption but deemed systematic oppression and organized fraud as impossible due to widely (and randomly) distributed power combined with checks-and-balances.[26] Furthermore, power did not tend to go to those who sought it. The Athenians used an intricate machine, a kleroterion, to allot officers. Headlam found the Athenians largely trusted the system of random selection, regarding it as the most natural and the simplest way of appointment.[27] While sortition was used for most positions, elections were sometimes used for positions like for military commanders (strategos).[28]

Lombardy and Venice – 12th to 18th century

The brevia was used in the city states of Lombardy during the 12th and 13th centuries and in Venice until the late 18th century.[29] Men, who were chosen randomly, swore an oath that they were not acting under bribes, and then they elected members of the council. Voter and candidate eligibility probably included property owners, councilors, guild members, and perhaps, at times, artisans. The Doge of Venice was determined through a complex process of nomination, voting and sortition.

Lot was used in the Venetian system only in order to select members of the committees that served to nominate candidates for the Great Council. A combination of election and lot was used in this multi-stage process. Lot was not used alone to select magistrates, unlike in Florence and Athens. The use of lot to select nominators made it more difficult for political sects to exert power, and discouraged campaigning.[23] By reducing intrigue and power moves within the Great Council, lot maintained cohesiveness among the Venetian nobility, contributing to the stability of this republic. Top magistracies generally still remained in the control of elite families.[30]

Florence – 14th and 15th century

Scrutiny was used in Florence for over a century starting in 1328.[29] Nominations and voting together created a pool of candidates from different sectors of the city. The names of these men were deposited into a sack, and a lottery draw determined who would get to be a magistrate. The scrutiny was gradually opened up to minor guilds, reaching the greatest level of Renaissance citizen participation in 1378–1382.

In Florence, lot was used to select magistrates and members of the Signoria during republican periods. Florence utilized a combination of lot and scrutiny by the people, set forth by the ordinances of 1328.[23] In 1494, Florence founded a Great Council in the model of Venice. The nominatori were thereafter chosen by lot from among the members of the Great Council, indicating an increase in aristocratic power.[31]

The Enlightenment

During the Age of Enlightenment, many of the political ideals originally championed by the democratic city-states of ancient Greece were revisited. The use of sortition as a means of selecting the members of government while receiving praise from notable Enlightenment thinkers, received almost no discussion during the formation of the American and French republics.

Montesquieu's book The Spirit of Laws provides one of the most cited discussions of the concept in Enlightenment political writing. In which, he argues sortition is natural to democracy, just as elections are to aristocracy.[32] He echoes the philosophy of much earlier thinkers such as Aristotle, who found elections as aristocratic.[33] Montesquieu caveats his support by saying that there should also be some mechanisms to ensure the pool of selection is competent and not corrupt.[34] Rousseau also found that a mixed model of sortition and election provided a healthier path for democracy than one or the other.[35] Harrington, also found the Venetian model of sortition compelling, recommending it for his ideal republic of Oceana.[36] Edmund Burke, in contrast, worried that those randomly selected to serve would be less effective and productive than self-selected politicians.[23][37][38]

Bernard Manin, a French political theorist, was astonished to find so little consideration of sortition in the early years of representative government. He wonders if perhaps the choosing of rulers by lot may have been viewed as impractical on such a large scale as the modern state, or if elections were thought to give greater political consent than sortition.[33]

However, David Van Reybrouck disagrees with Manin's theories on the lack of consideration of sortition. He suggests that the relatively limited knowledge about Athenian democracy played a major role, with the first thorough examination coming only in 1891 with Election by Lot at Athens. He also argues that wealthy enlightenment figures preferred to retain more power by holding elections, with most not even offering excuses on the basis of practicality but plainly saying they preferred to retain significant elite power,[39] citing commentators of 18th century France and the United States suggesting that they simply dislodged a hereditary aristocracy to replace it with an elected aristocracy.[40]

Switzerland

Because financial gain could be achieved through the position of mayor, some parts of Switzerland used random selection during the years between 1640 and 1837 to prevent corruption.[41]

Methods

USCAR Court select juries by sortition

Before the random selection can be done, the pool of candidates must be defined. Systems vary as to whether they allot from eligible volunteers, from those screened by education, experience, or a passing grade on a test, or screened by election by those selected by a previous round of random selection, or from the membership or population at large. A multi-stage process in which random selection is alternated with other screening methods can be used, as in the Venetian system.

One method allows for multiple specific sources of random numbers (e.g., lotteries) to be selected in advance, and an algorithm is defined for selecting the winners based on those random numbers. When the random numbers become available, anyone can calculate the winners.[42][non-primary source needed] David Chaum proposed selecting a random sample of eligible voters to study and vote on a public policy,[43] while Deliberative opinion polling has been used in many instances to inform or even make decisions in Greece, China and other countries.[44]

Analysis

A critique of electoral politics is the over-representation of politically active groups in society who tend to be those who join political parties.[45][28] For example, in 2000 less than 2%[46] of the UK population belonged to a political party, while in 2005 there were at best only 3 independent MPs (see List of UK minor party and independent MPs elected) so that 99.5% of all UK MPs belonged to a political party. Cognitive diversity is an amalgamation of different ways of seeing the world and interpreting events within it,[47] where a diversity of perspectives and heuristics guide individuals to create different solutions to the same problems.[48] Cognitive diversity is not the same as gender, ethnicity, value-set or age diversity, although they are often positively correlated. According to numerous scholars such as Page and Landemore,[49] cognitive diversity is more important to creating successful ideas than the average ability level of a group. This "diversity trumps ability theorem"[50] is essential to why sortition is a viable democratic option.[48] Simply put, random selection of persons of average intelligence performs better than a collection of the best individual problem solvers.[48]

Magnus Vinding in his book Reasoned Politics argues that sortition is more efficient by allowing decision-makers to focus on positive-sum endeavors rather than zero-sum elections.[51] This shift towards issues and away from elections could help to lessen political polarization[51] and the influence of money and interest-groups in politics.[40] Adam Grant cites findings by Alexander Haslam showing more altruism in randomly-selected decision-makers as well as other studies showing an overrepresentation of psychopathic and narcissistic traits in elected officials.[52]

A modern advocate of sortition, political scientist John Burnheim, notes the importance of legitimacy for the effectiveness of the practice.[53] Legitimacy does depend on the success in achieving representativeness, which if not met, could limit the use cases of sortition to serving as consultative or political agenda-setting bodies.[54] Oliver Dowlen points to the egalitarian nature of all citizens having an equal chance of entering office irrespective of any bias in society that appear in representative bodies that can make them more representative.[55][56] To bolster legitimacy, other sortition bodies have been used and proposed to set the rules to improve accountability without the need for elections.[57] The introduction of a variable percentage of randomly selected independent legislators in a Parliament can increase the global efficiency of a legislature, in terms of both number of laws passed and average social welfare obtained[58] (this work is consistent with a 2010 paper on how the adoption of random strategies can improve the efficiency of hierarchical organizations[59]).[60]

As participants grow in competence by contributing to deliberation, they also become more engaged and interested in civic affairs.[61] Most societies have some type of citizenship education, but sortition-based committees allow ordinary people to develop their own democratic capacities through direct participation.[62]

Modern application

Sortition is most commonly used to form citizens' assemblies. The OECD has counted almost 600 examples of citizens' assemblies with members selected by lottery for public decision making.[2] As an example, Vancouver council initiated a citizens' assembly that met in 2014–15 in order to assist in city planning.[63]

Drawing straws within a small group: one of four matches is broken to be shorter than the others, and the four are presented to the group to draw from, the chooser of the short match being selected

Sortition is commonly used in selecting juries in Anglo-Saxon[64] legal systems and in small groups (e.g., picking a school class monitor by drawing straws). In public decision-making, individuals are often determined by allotment if other forms of selection such as election fail to achieve a result. Examples include certain hung elections and certain votes in the UK Parliament. Some contemporary thinkers like David Van Reybrouck have advocated a greater use of selection by lot in today's political systems.

Sortition is also used in military conscription, as one method of awarding US green cards, and in placing students into some schools, university classes, and university residences.[65][66]

Non-governmental organizations

Sortition also has potential for helping large associations to govern themselves democratically without the use of elections. Co-ops, employee-owned businesses, housing associations, Internet platforms, student governments, and countless other large membership organizations whose members generally do not know many other members yet seek to run their organization democratically often find elections problematic.[67][68] The essential leadership decisions are made by the nomination process, often generating a self-perpetuating board whose nominating committee selects their own successors. Randomly selecting a representative sample of members to constitute a nominating panel is one procedure that has been proposed to keep fundamental control in the hands of ordinary members and avoid internal board corruption.[69] For example, The Samaritan Ministries Health Plan sometimes uses a panel of 13 randomly selected members to resolve disputes, which sometimes leads to policy changes.[70] Also, Democracy In Practice, an international organization dedicated to democratic innovation, experimentation and capacity-building, has implemented sortition in schools in Bolivia, replacing student government elections with lotteries.[71] Lastly, in 2013 the New Zealand Health Research council began awarding funding at random to applicants considered equally qualified.[72]

Public policy

Main page: Social:Citizens' assembly

Perhaps the most common example in practice today, are law court juries which are formed through sortition in some countries, such as the United States and United Kingdom. An increasingly common set of examples includes Citizens' assemblies, which have been used to provide input to policy makers all across the globe, including in countries like Ireland and Denmark.

In 2019, the German speaking Ostbelgien region in Belgium, implemented the Ostbelgien Model, consisting of an 24-member Citizen's Council which convenes short term Citizen's Assemblies to provide non-binding recommendations to its parliament.[73] Later that same year both the main and French-speaking parliaments of the Brussels-Capital Region voted to authorize setting up mixed parliamentary committees composed of parliamentarians and randomly selected citizens to draft recommendations on a given issue.[74] The Amish have used sortition to a slate of nominees when they select their community leaders. In their process, formal members of the community each register a single private nomination, and candidates with a minimum threshold of nominations then stand for the random selection that follows.[75] Local government in parts of Tamil Nadu such as the village of Uttiramerur traditionally used a system known as kuda-olai where the names of candidates for the village committee were written on palm leaves and put into a pot and pulled out by a child.[76]

Political proposals for sortition

Supplement legislatures

Political scientist Robert A. Dahl suggests that an advanced democratic state could form groups which he calls minipopuli. Each group would consist of perhaps a thousand citizens randomly selected, and would either set an agenda of issues or deal with a particular major issue. It would hold hearings, commission research, and engage in debate and discussion. Dahl suggests having the minipopuli as supplementing, rather than replacing, legislative bodies.[77] Claudia Chwalisz has also advocated for using citizens' assemblies selected by sortition to inform policymaking on an ongoing basis.[78][79][80][81]

Replace legislatures

John Burnheim envisions a political system in which many small citizens' juries would deliberate and make decisions about public policies.[82] His proposal includes the dissolution of the state and of bureaucracies. The term demarchy he uses was coined by Friedrich Hayek for a different proposal,[83] unrelated to sortition, and is now sometimes used to refer to any political system in which sortition plays a central role.[84] L. León coined the word lottocracy for a sortition procedure that is somewhat different from Burnheim's demarchy.[85] While Burnheim preferred using only volunteers,[86] León says "that first of all, the job must not be liked".[87] Christopher Frey uses the German term Lottokratie and recommends testing lottocracy in town councils. Lottocracy, according to Frey, will improve the direct involvement of each citizen and minimize the systematical errors caused by political parties in Europe.[88] Influenced by Burnheim, Marxist economists Paul Cockshott and Allin Cottrell propose that, to avoid formation of a new social elite in a post-capitalist society, citizens' committees chosen by lot (or partially chosen by lot) should make major decisions.[89]

Constitutional changes are one of the most common to solicit input via sortition. Étienne Chouard advocates strongly that those seeking power (elected officials) should not write the rules, making sortition an essential choice for creating constitutions.[90] He and others propose replacing elections with bodies that use sortition to decide on key issues.[91][92][93][37]

Choose some legislators and public officials

Proposed changes to the legislature of the Parliament of Tasmania: A single legislative body of 50–100 people is selected randomly from the population and makes laws. One of their duties is the selection of seven members of an executive council.

Simon Threlkeld proposed a wide range of public officials be chosen by randomly sampled juries, rather than by politicians or popular election.[94] Michael Donovan proposes that the percentage of voters who do not turnout have their representatives chosen by sortition. For example, with 60% voter turnout a number of legislators are randomly chosen to make up 40% of the overall parliament.[95]

A number of proposals for an entire legislative body to be chosen by sortition have been made for the United States,[96][97] Canada,[98][99] the United Kingdom,[100][101][102] Denmark,[103] and France.[104][105]

See also

References

  1. Engelstad, Fredrik (1989). "The assignment of political office by lot". Social Science Information 28 (1): 23–50. doi:10.1177/053901889028001002. 
  2. 2.0 2.1 OECD (2020) (in en). Innovative Citizen Participation and New Democratic Institutions: Catching the Deliberative Wave. Paris: Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development. doi:10.1787/339306da-en. ISBN 9789264837621. https://www.oecd-ilibrary.org/governance/innovative-citizen-participation-and-new-democratic-institutions_339306da-en. 
  3. Landemore, Hélène (January 15, 2010). "Deliberation, Representation, and the Epistemic Function of Parliamentary Assemblies: a Burkean Argument in Favor of Descriptive Representation". International Conference on "Democracy as Idea and Practice", University of Oslo, Oslo January 13–15, 2010. https://www.uio.no/english/research/interfaculty-research-areas/democracy/news-and-events/events/conferences/2010/papers/Landemore-DeliberationRepresentation-2010.pdf. 
  4. Graeber, David (2013-04-09). The Democracy Project: A History, a Crisis, a Movement. Random House Inc. pp. 957–959. ISBN 978-0-679-64600-6. https://archive.org/details/isbn_9780812993561/page/957. Retrieved 1 October 2018. 
  5. Headlam, James Wycliffe (1891). Election by Lot at Athens. The University Press. p. 12. https://archive.org/details/electionbylotat00headgoog. 
  6. Cambiano, Giuseppe (2020). "Piccola archeologia del sorteggio" (in it). Teoria Politica (10): 103–121. http://journals.openedition.org/tp/1106. 
  7. Flanigan, Bailey; Gölz, Paul; Gupta, Anupam; Hennig, Brett; Procaccia, Ariel D. (2021). "Fair algorithms for selecting citizens' assemblies". Nature 596 (7873): 548–552. doi:10.1038/s41586-021-03788-6. PMID 34349266. Bibcode2021Natur.596..548F. 
  8. Fishkin, James (2009). When the People Speak: Deliberative Democracy & Public Consultation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199604432. https://archive.org/details/whenpeoplespeakd00fish_1. 
  9. Ostfeld, Jacob (2020-11-19). "The Case for Sortition in America" (in en-US). https://harvardpolitics.com/sortition-in-america/. 
  10. Reybrouck, David Van (2016-06-29). "Why elections are bad for democracy" (in en-GB). The Guardian. ISSN 0261-3077. https://www.theguardian.com/politics/2016/jun/29/why-elections-are-bad-for-democracy. 
  11. Rieg, Timo; Translated from German by Catherine McLean (Sep 8, 2015). "Why a citizen's parliament chosen by lot would be 'perfect'" (in en). https://www.swissinfo.ch/eng/opinion_why-a-citizen-s-parliament-chosen-by-lot-would-be-perfect/41646866. 
  12. Wolfson, Arthur M. (1899). "The Ballot and Other Forms of Voting in the Italian Communes". The American Historical Review 5 (1): 1–21. doi:10.2307/1832957. 
  13. 13.0 13.1 13.2 The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes, Mogens Herman Hansen, ISBN:1-85399-585-1
  14. Aristotle, Politics 1301a28-35
  15. Aristotle, Politics 4.1294be
  16. Plato, Republic VIII, 557a
  17. Herodotus The Histories 3.80.6
  18. Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War. The Funeral Oration of Pericles.
  19. Xenophon. Memorabilia Book I, 2.9
  20. Isocrates. Areopagiticus (section 23)
  21. Bernard Manin, The Principles of Representative Government
  22. Shapiro, Jessica Mellenthin and Susan O. (in en). Poseidon. Mythology Unbound: An Online Textbook for Classical Mythology. https://uen.pressbooks.pub/mythologyunbound/chapter/poseidon/. 
  23. 23.0 23.1 23.2 23.3 Manin, Bernard (1997). The Principles of Representative Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-45891-7. 
  24. Hansen, M. H. (1981). Election by Lot at Athens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 
  25. Dibble, Julian. "Info Tech of Ancient Democracy". http://www.alamut.com/subj/artiface/deadMedia/agoraMuseum.html. 
  26. Headlam, James Wycliffe (1891). Election by Lot at Athens. The University Press. p. 77. https://archive.org/details/electionbylotat00headgoog. 
  27. Headlam, James Wycliffe (1891). Election by Lot at Athens. The University Press. p. 96. https://archive.org/details/electionbylotat00headgoog. 
  28. 28.0 28.1 Tangian, Andranik (2020). "Chapter 1 Athenian democracy″ and ″Chapter 6 Direct democracy". Analytical theory of democracy. Vols. 1 and 2. Studies in Choice and Welfare. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. pp. 3–43, 263–315. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-39691-6. ISBN 978-3-030-39690-9. 
  29. 29.0 29.1 Dowlen, Oliver (2008). The Political Potential of Sortition: A study of the random selection of citizens for public office. Imprint Academic. 
  30. Rousseau (1762). On the Social Contract. New York: St Martin's Press. p. 112. 
  31. Brucker, Gene (1962). Florentine Politics and Society 1342–1378. Princeton: Princeton University Press. 
  32. Montesquieu (2001). De l'esprit des lois. Batoche Books, Kitchener. 
  33. 33.0 33.1 Manin, Bernard (1997). The principles of representative government. Cambridge. ISBN 978-1-4619-4910-7. OCLC 861693063. https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/861693063. 
  34. Manin, Bernard (1997). The principles of representative government. Cambridge. pp. 71. ISBN 978-1-4619-4910-7. OCLC 861693063. https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/861693063. 
  35. Van Reybrouck, David (2016). Against elections : the case for democracy. Kofi A. Annan, Liz Waters (First US ed.). New York. pp. 74–75. ISBN 978-1-60980-811-2. OCLC 1029781182. https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/1029781182. 
  36. Manin, Bernard (1997). The Principles of Representative Government. Cambridge. pp. 63. ISBN 978-1-4619-4910-7. OCLC 861693063. https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/861693063. 
  37. 37.0 37.1 Bouricius, Terrill (30 April 2013). "Democracy Through Multi-Body Sortition: Athenian Lessons for the Modern Day". Journal of Public Deliberation 9 (1). doi:10.16997/jdd.156. https://www.publicdeliberation.net/jpd/vol9/iss1/art11. 
  38. Edmund Burke (1790), Reflections on the Revolution in France
  39. Van Reybrouck, David (2016). Against Elections: the case for democracy. Seven Stories Press. pp. 75–78. ISBN 978-1-60980-811-2. OCLC 1048327708. http://worldcat.org/oclc/1048327708. 
  40. 40.0 40.1 Reybrouck, David van (2016). Against elections: the case for democracy. London: The Bodley Head. pp. 85. ISBN 978-1-84792-422-3. 
  41. Carson, Lyn; Martin, Brian (1999). Random Selection in Politics. Praeger. p. 33. 
  42. ((Eastlake 3rd)), Donald E. (June 2004). Publicly Verifiable Nominations Committee (NomCom) Random Selection (Report). Internet Engineering Task Force. doi:10.17487/rfc3797. https://datatracker.ietf.org/doc/rfc3797/. 
  43. David Chaum (2012). "Random-Sample Elections: Far lower cost, better quality and more democratic". http://rsvoting.org/whitepaper/white_paper.pdf. 
  44. Davis, Joshua (2012-05-16). "How Selecting Voters Randomly Can Lead to Better Elections". Wired. https://www.wired.com/2012/05/st-essay-voting/. Retrieved 2020-12-02. 
  45. Tangian, Andranik (2008). "A mathematical model of Athenian democracy". Social Choice and Welfare 31 (4): 537–572. doi:10.1007/s00355-008-0295-y. 
  46. Tom Bentley; Paul Miller (September 24, 2004). "The decline of the political party". http://www.perfect.co.uk/2004/09/the-decline-of-the-political-party. 
  47. Landemore, Hélène (2012). "Deliberation, Cognitive Diversity, and Democratic Inclusiveness: An Epistemic Argument for the Random Selection of Representatives". Synthese 190 (7): 1209–1231. doi:10.1007/s11229-012-0062-6. 
  48. 48.0 48.1 48.2 Page (2007). How the power of diversity creates better groups, firms, schools, and societies.. Princeton University Press. 
  49. Bouricious, Terrill (2013). "Democracy Through Multi-Body Sortition: Athenian Lessons for the Modern Day". Journal of Public Deliberation 9 (1): Article 11. http://www.publicdeliberation.net/jpd/vol9/iss1/art11. Retrieved 2019-06-04. 
  50. Dreifus, Claudia (January 8, 2008). "In Professor's Model, Diversity = Productivity". The New York Times. https://www.nytimes.com/2008/01/08/science/08conv.html. 
  51. 51.0 51.1 Vinding, Magnus (2022). "14: Democracy". Reasoned Politics. Copenhagen: Ratio Ethica. pp. 225–226. ISBN 9798790852930. 
  52. Grant, Adam (2023-08-21). "Opinion | The Worst People Run for Office. It's Time for a Better Way." (in en-US). The New York Times. ISSN 0362-4331. https://www.nytimes.com/2023/08/21/opinion/elections-democracy.html. 
  53. Burnheim, John (2006). Is Democracy Possible?. University of California Press. pp. 124–125. ISBN 978-1920898427. 
  54. Lafont, Cristina (2015-03-01). "Deliberation, Participation, and Democratic Legitimacy: Should Deliberative Mini-publics Shape Public Policy?" (in en). Journal of Political Philosophy 23 (1): 40–63. doi:10.1111/jopp.12031. ISSN 1467-9760. 
  55. Delannoi, Gil; Dowlen, Oliver (2016-10-05) (in en). Sortition: Thoery and Practice. Andrews UK Limited. ISBN 978-1-84540-700-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=V3nZCgAAQBAJ&dq=Sortition+qi&pg=PP31. 
  56. Dowlen, Oliver (June 2009). "Sorting Out Sortition: A Perspective on the Random Selection of Political Officers" (in en). Political Studies 57 (2): 298–315. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.2008.00746.x. ISSN 0032-3217. http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2008.00746.x. 
  57. Manin, Bernard (1997). The principles of representative government. Cambridge. p. 56. ISBN 978-1-4619-4910-7. OCLC 861693063. https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/861693063. 
  58. Pluchino, A.; Garofalo, C.; Rapisarda, A.; Spagano, S.; Caserta, M. (October 2011). "Accidental Politicians: How Randomly Selected Legislators Can Improve Parliament Efficiency". Physica A: Statistical Mechanics and its Applications 390 (21–22): 3944–3954. doi:10.1016/j.physa.2011.06.028. Bibcode2011PhyA..390.3944P. 
  59. Pluchino, Alessandro; Rapisarda, Andrea; Garofalo, Cesare (February 2010). "The Peter Principle Revisited: A Computational Study". Physica A: Statistical Mechanics and its Applications 389 (3): 467–472. doi:10.1016/j.physa.2009.09.045. Bibcode2010PhyA..389..467P. 
  60. Caserta, Maurizio; Pluchino, Alessandro; Rapisarda, Andrea; Spagano, Salvatore (2021). "Why lot? How sortition could help representative democracy". Physica A: Statistical Mechanics and its Applications 565: 125430. doi:10.1016/j.physa.2020.125430. Bibcode2021PhyA..56525430C. 
  61. (in en) Sortition as a sustainable protection against oligarchy, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=KsnNpcJtwoo, retrieved 2023-02-24 . Talk by Étienne Chouard. At 0:17:10
  62. Zaphir, Luke (2017). "Democratic communities of inquiry: Creating opportunities to develop citizenship". Educational Philosophy and Theory 50 (4): 359–368. doi:10.1080/00131857.2017.1364156. 
  63. "City of Vancouver Grandview-Woodland Community Plan". http://grandview-woodland.ca/. 
  64. Carson, Lyn; Martin, Brian (1999-12-30) (in en). Random Selection in Politics. Bloomsbury Academic. ISBN 978-0-275-96702-4. https://books.google.com.sl/books/about/Random_Selection_in_Politics.html?hl=fr&id=kRmGAAAAMAAJ&output=html_text. 
  65. Boyle, Conall (2010). Lotteries for Education. Exeter: Imprint Academic. 
  66. Stone, Peter (2011). The Luck of the Draw: The Role of Lotteries in Decision Making. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780199756100. 
  67. Kennedy, Jeffrey; Pek, Simon (2023-01-02). "Mini-publics, student participation, and universities’ deliberative capacity" (in en). Studies in Higher Education 48 (1): 63–82. doi:10.1080/03075079.2022.2111551. ISSN 0307-5079. https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/03075079.2022.2111551. 
  68. Pek, Simon (2023-12-15). "Reconceptualizing and Improving Member Participation in Large Cooperatives: Insights from Deliberative Democracy and Deliberative Mini-Publics" (in en). M@n@gement: 68–82. doi:10.37725/mgmt.2023.8478. ISSN 1286-4692. https://management-aims.com/index.php/mgmt/article/view/8478. 
  69. Terry Bouricius (April 19, 2017). "A Better Co-op Democracy Without Elections?". https://blog.p2pfoundation.net/a-better-co-op-democracy-without-elections/2017/04/19. 
  70. Leonard, Kimberly (2016-02-23). "Christians Find Their Own Way to Replace Obamacare". https://www.usnews.com/news/articles/2016-02-23/membership-for-health-sharing-ministries-soars-under-obamacare. 
  71. "Participedia, Democracy In Practice: Democratic Student Government Program". February 2014. http://participedia.net/en/cases/democracy-practice-democratic-student-government-program-cochabamba-bolivia. 
  72. Liu M, Choy V, Clarke P, Barnett A, Blakely T, Pomeroy L (2020). "The acceptability of using a lottery to allocate research funding: a survey of applicants.". Res Integr Peer Rev 5: 3. doi:10.1186/s41073-019-0089-z. PMID 32025338. 
  73. "The Ostbelgien Model: a long-term Citizens' Council combined with short-term Citizens' Assemblies". https://oidp.net/en/practice.php?id=1237. 
  74. "Belgium's experiment in permanent forms of deliberative democracy". https://constitutionnet.org/news/belgiums-experiment-permanent-forms-deliberative-democracy. 
  75. B., Kraybill, Donald (2013). The Amish. Johnson-Weiner, Karen., Nolt, Steven M., 1968–. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN 9781421409146. OCLC 810329297. 
  76. "Encyclopedia of Hinduism". http://theencyclopediaofhinduism.tumblr.com/post/104798277303/uttaramerur-a-village-near-kanchipuram-in-the. 
  77. Dahl, Robert A.. Democracy and its Critics. pp. 340. 
  78. Chwalisz, Claudia (2015). The populist signal: why politics and democracy need to change. London New York: Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-1-78348-542-0. 
  79. Chwalisz, Claudia (2017). The People's Verdict: adding informed citizen voices to public decision-making. Policy Network. London New York: Policy Network/Rowman & Littlefield International. ISBN 978-1-78660-436-1. 
  80. OECD (2021-12-14) (in en). Eight ways to institutionalise deliberative democracy. OECD Public Governance Policy Papers. Paris. doi:10.1787/4fcf1da5-en. https://www.oecd-ilibrary.org/governance/eight-ways-to-institutionalise-deliberative-democracy_4fcf1da5-en. 
  81. Chwalisz, Claudia (2023-06-29). "Assembly required - RSA Comment" (in en). https://www.thersa.org/comment/2023/06/assembly-required. 
  82. Burnheim, John. Is Democracy Possible?. 
  83. Friedrich August von Hayek: Law, legislation and liberty, Volume 3, pp. 38–40.
  84. Burnheim, John (1985). Is Democracy Possible?. University of California Press. 
  85. León, L (1988). The World-Solution for World-Problems: The Problem, Its Cause, Its Solution. L. León. ISBN 978-90-900259-2-6. http://www.socsci.ru.nl/advdv/leonbook/leonbook.html. 
  86. Brian Martin (Fall 1992). "Demarchy: A Democratic Alternative to Electoral Politics". Kick It Over (30): 11–13. http://www.uow.edu.au/arts/sts/bmartin/pubs/92kio.html. 
  87. The World Solution for World Problems, Chapter: A Concept for Government, León
  88. Christopher Frey (16 June 2009). Lottokratie: Entwurf einer postdemokratischen Gesellschaft. Geschichte der Zukunft, volume 4. Books on Demand. ISBN:978-3-83-910540-5
  89. Cockshott, William Paul; Cottrell, Allin F. (1993). Towards a New Socialism. Spokesman Books. ISBN 978-0851245454. 
  90. (in en) Sortition as a sustainable protection against oligarchy, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=KsnNpcJtwoo, retrieved 2023-02-24 . Talk by Étienne Chouard. 0:43:03
  91. ""Populiste n'est pas un gros mot", entretien avec Etienne Chouard" (in fr). August 24, 2012. http://ragemag.fr/populiste-nest-pas-un-gros-mot-entretien-avec-etienne-chouard. 
  92. "YouTube". https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=0e22oUvDSwM. 
  93. Threlkeld, Simon (Summer 1998). "A Blueprint for Democratic Law-Making: Give Citizen Juries the Final Say". Social Policy: 5–9. https://equalitybylot.com/2015/11/06/threlkeld-juries-not-referenda/. 
  94. Threlkeld, Simon (Summer 1997). "Democratizing Public Institutions: Juries for the selection of public officials". Humanist in Canada (120): 24–25, 33. https://equalitybylot.com/2015/11/08/threlkeld-democratizing-public-institutions/. 
  95. Donovan, Michael (2012). Political Sortition for an Evolving World. Simon Fraser University. p. 83. http://summit.sfu.ca/item/12579. 
  96. James, C. L. R.. "Every Cook Can Govern". https://www.marxists.org/archive/james-clr/works/1956/06/every-cook.htm. 
  97. Callenbach, Ernest; Phillips, Michael (1985). A Citizen Legislature. Berkeley/Bodega California: Banyan Tree Books / Clear Glass. http://www.well.com/~mp/citleg.html. 
  98. Mitchell, Jack; Mitchell, David (22 September 2005). "Athens on the Hill: A plan for a Neo-Athenian Parliament in Canada". National Post. pp. A23. 
  99. Abizadeh, Arash (2016). "Opinion: Let's replace Canada's Senate with a randomly selected citizen assembly". https://montrealgazette.com/opinion/columnists/opinion-lets-replace-canadas-senate-with-a-randomly-selected-citizen-assembly. 
  100. Barnett, Anthony; Carty, Peter (2008). The Athenian Option: Radical Reform for the House of Lords (2nd ed.). Imprint Academic. 
  101. Sutherland, Keith (2008). A People's Parliament. Imprint Academic. 
  102. "Let The People Wear Ermine If We Are to Abolish the House of Lords". 2015-08-18. Archived from the original on 2016-08-07. https://web.archive.org/web/20160807170921/http://www.disclaimermag.com/politics/let-the-people-wear-ermine-if-we-are-to-abolish-the-house-of-lords-2792. 
  103. Ellersgaard, Christoph Houman; Larsen, Anton Grau; Mulvad, Andreas Møller. "Centrum-venstre skal tøjle eliten og give borgerne større indflydelse" (in da-DK). Politiken. https://politiken.dk/debat/art6113441/Centrum-venstre-skal-t%C3%B8jle-eliten-og-give-borgerne-st%C3%B8rre-indflydelse. 
  104. "The campaign beat – Jean-Luc Mélenchon's call for a Sixth Republic" (in en). 2017-04-12. https://www.france24.com/en/20170412-presidential-election-polls-jean-luc-melenchon-francois-hollande. 
  105. "L'urgence démocratique – La 6e République" (in fr). http://laec.fr/chapitre/1/la-6e-republique. 

External links