Astronomy:Microcosm-macrocosm analogy

From HandWiki
Revision as of 16:21, 6 March 2023 by Carolyn (talk | contribs) (link)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Short description: Analogy between man and cosmos
From Robert Fludd, Utriusque cosmi historia, Oppenheim/Frankfurt, 1617–1621.

The microcosm-macrocosm analogy (or, equivalently, macrocosm-microcosm analogy) refers to a historical view which posited a structural similarity between the human being (the microcosm, i.e., the small order or the small universe) and the cosmos as a whole (the macrocosm, i.e., the great order or the great universe).[1] Given this fundamental analogy, truths about the nature of the cosmos as a whole may be inferred from truths about human nature, and vice versa.[2]

One important corollary of this view is that the cosmos as a whole may be considered to be alive, and thus to have a mind or soul (the world soul), a position advanced by Plato in his Timaeus.[3] Moreover, this cosmic mind or soul was often thought to be divine, most notably by the Stoics and those who were influenced by them, such as the authors of the Hermetica.[4] Hence, it was sometimes inferred that the human mind or soul too was divine in nature.

Apart from this important psychological and noetic (i.e., related to the mind) application, the analogy was also applied to human physiology.[5] For example, the cosmological functions of the seven classical planets were sometimes taken to be analogous to the physiological functions of human organs, such as the heart, the spleen, the liver, the stomach, etc.[6]

The view itself is ancient, and may be found in many philosophical systems world-wide, such as for example in ancient Mesopotamia,[7] in ancient Iran,[8] or in ancient Chinese philosophy.[9] However, the terms microcosm and macrocosm refer more specifically to the analogy as it was developed in ancient Greek philosophy and its medieval and early modern descendants.

In contemporary usage, the terms microcosm and macrocosm are also employed to refer to any smaller system that is representative of a larger one, and vice versa.

History

Zeno of Citium (c. 334–262 BCE), founder of the Stoic school of philosophy.

Antiquity

Among ancient Greek and Hellenistic philosophers, notable proponents of the microcosm-macrocosm analogy included Anaximander (c. 610 – c. 546 BCE),[10] Plato (c. 428 or 424 – c. 348 BCE),[11] the Hippocratic authors (late fifth or early fourth century BCE and onwards),[12] and the Stoics (third century BCE and onwards).[13] In later periods, the analogy was especially prominent in the works of those philosophers who were heavily influenced by Platonic and Stoic thought, such as Philo of Alexandria (c. 20 BCE – c. 50 CE),[14] the authors of the early Greek Hermetica (c. 100 BCE – c. 300 CE),[15] and the Neoplatonists (third century CE and onwards).[16] The analogy also started occurring from an early date in religious literature, such as in the Zoroastrian encyclopedic work called the Bundahishn, or in the early Rabbinical text called the Avot de-Rabbi Nathan.[17]

Middle Ages

Medieval philosophy was generally dominated by Aristotle, who despite having been the first to coin the term "microcosm",[18] had posited a fundamental and insurmountable difference between the region below the moon (the sublunary world, consisting of the four elements) and the region above the moon (the superlunary world, consisting of a fifth element). Nevertheless, the microcosm-macrocosm analogy was adopted by a wide variety of medieval thinkers working in different linguistic traditions: the concept of microcosm was known in Arabic as ʿālam ṣaghīr, in Hebrew as olam katan, and in Latin as microcosmus or minor mundus.[19] The analogy was elaborated by alchemists such as those writing under the name of Jabir ibn Hayyan (c. 850–950 CE),[20] by the anonymous Shi'ite philosophers known as the Ikhwān al-Ṣafāʾ ("The Brethren of Purity", c. 900–1000 CE),[21] by Jewish theologians and philosophers such as Isaac Israeli (c. 832–932), Saadia Gaon (882/892–942), Ibn Gabirol (11th century), and Judah Halevi (c. 1075–1141),[22] by the Andalusian mystic Ibn Arabi (1165–1240),[23] and by the German cardinal Nicholas of Cusa (1401–1464).[24]

Renaissance

Paracelsus (1494–1541)

The revival of Hermeticism and Neoplatonism in the Renaissance, both of which had reserved a prominent place for the microcosm-macrocosm analogy, also led to a marked rise in popularity of the latter. Some of the most notable proponents of the concept in this period include Marsilio Ficino (1433–1499), Heinrich Cornelius Agrippa (1486–1535), Francesco Patrizi (1529–1597), Giordano Bruno (1548–1600), and Tommaso Campanella (1568–1639).[25] It was also central to the new medical theories propounded by the Swiss physician Paracelsus (1494–1541) and his many followers, most notably Robert Fludd (1574–1637).[26] Andreas Vesalius (1514–1564) in his anatomy text De fabrica wrote that the human body "in many respects corresponds admirably to the universe and for that reason was called the little universe by the ancients."[27]

See also

References

  1. The terms microcosm and macrocosm derive from ancient Greek μικρός κόσμος (mikrós kósmos) and μακρός κόσμος (makrós kósmos), which may mean 'small universe' and 'great universe', but whose primary meaning is 'small order' and 'great order', respectively (see wiktionary; cf. Allers 1944, pp. 320-321, note 5).
  2. On the macrocosm and the microcosm in general, see, e.g., Conger 1922; Allers 1944; Barkan 1975.
  3. See Olerud 1951.
  4. On the Stoics, see Hahm 1977, 63ff.; on the Hermetica, see Festugière 1944–1954, vol. I, pp. 92-94, 125-131.
  5. See, e.g., Kranz 1938, pp. 130–133.
  6. See the drawing shown on the right (from Robert Fludd's Utriusque cosmi historia, 1617–1621), which correlates the sun (considered to be a planet in the geocentric model) with the heart.
  7. Svärd & Nokso-Koivisto 2014.
  8. Götze 1923; Duchesne-Guillemin 1956.
  9. Raphals 2015–2020.
  10. See, e.g., Allers 1944.
  11. See especially Olerud 1951.
  12. See Kranz 1938; Schluderer 2018.
  13. See Hahm 1977, 63ff.
  14. See, e.g., Runia 1986, pp. 87, 133, 157, 211, 259, 278, 282, 315, 324, 339, 388, 465-466.
  15. See Festugière 1944–1954, vol. I, pp. 92-94, 125-131.
  16. See, e.g., Wilberding 2006, pp. 53–56.
  17. Jacobs & Broydé 1906; Kraemer 2007.
  18. Kraemer 2007, p. 178.
  19. Kraemer 2007, p. 178; on the Latin terminology, see Finckh 1999, p. 12.
  20. Kraus 1942–1943, vol. II, pp. 47, 50.
  21. See, e.g., Widengren 1980; Nokso-Koivisto 2014; Krinis 2016.
  22. Jacobs & Broydé 1906; Kraemer 2007.
  23. Aminrazavi 2009–2021.
  24. Miller 2009–2017.
  25. See the discussion in Allers 1944, pp. 386–401.
  26. Debus 1965, pp. 19, 41-42, 86, 114-123, et passim.
  27. O'Malley 1964, p. 324.

Further reading

Other sources cited