Finance:Efficiency wage

From HandWiki
Revision as of 17:18, 5 February 2024 by NBrush (talk | contribs) (simplify)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Short description: Wage per efficiency unit of labor


The term efficiency wages (also known as "efficiency earnings") was introduced by Alfred Marshall to denote the wage per efficiency unit of labor.[1] Marshallian efficiency wages are those calculated with efficiency or ability exerted being the unit of measure rather than time.[1] That is, the more efficient worker will be paid more than a less efficient worker for the same amount of hours worked.[1]

The modern use of the term is quite different and refers to the idea that higher wages may increase the efficiency of the workers by various channels, making it worthwhile for the employers to offer wages that exceed a market-clearing level. Optimal efficiency wage is achieved when the marginal cost of an increase in wages is equal to the marginal benefit of improved productivity to an employer.[2]

In labor economics, the "efficiency wage" hypothesis argues that wages, at least in some labour markets, form in a way that is not market-clearing.[citation needed] Specifically, it points to the incentive for managers to pay their employees more than the market-clearing wage to increase their productivity or efficiency, or to reduce costs associated with employee turnover in industries in which the costs of replacing labor are high. The increased labor productivity and/or decreased costs may pay for the higher wages. Companies tend to hire workers at lower costs, but workers expect to be paid more when they work. The labor market balances the needs of employees and companies, so wages can fluctuate up or down.[3][page needed]

Because workers are paid more than the equilibrium wage, there may be unemployment, as the above-market wage rates attract more workers.[citation needed] Efficiency wages offer, therefore, a market failure explanation of unemployment in contrast to theories that emphasize government intervention such as minimum wages.[2] However, efficiency wages do not necessarily imply unemployment but only uncleared markets and job rationing in those markets.[citation needed] There may be full employment in the economy or yet efficiency wages may prevail in some occupations. In this case there will be excess supply for those occupations and some applicants whom are not hired may have to work at a lower wage elsewhere. Conversely, if supply is less than demand, some employers will need to hire employees at higher wages, and applicants can get jobs with wages higher than the considered wages.

Overview of theory

There are several theories (or "microfoundations") of why managers pay efficiency wages:

  • Avoiding shirking: If it is difficult to measure the quantity or quality of a worker's effort—and systems of piece rates or commissions are impossible, there may be an incentive for the worker to "shirk" (do less work than agreed). The manager thus may pay an efficiency wage in order to create or increase the cost of job loss, which gives a sting to the threat of firing. This threat can be used to prevent shirking.[citation needed]
  • Minimizing turnover: By paying above-market wages, the worker's motivation to leave the job and look for a job elsewhere will be reduced. This strategy also reduces the expense of training replacement workers.[citation needed]
  • Selection: If job performance depends on workers' ability and workers differ from each other in those terms, firms with higher wages will attract more able job-seekers, and this may make it profitable to offer wages that exceed the market clearing level.[citation needed]
  • Sociological theories: Efficiency wages may result from traditions. Akerlof's theory (in very simple terms) involves higher wages encouraging high morale, which raises productivity.[citation needed]
  • Nutritional theories: In developing countries, efficiency wages may allow workers to eat well enough to avoid illness and to be able to work harder and even more productively.[citation needed]

The model of efficiency wages, largely based on shirking, developed by Carl Shapiro and Joseph E. Stiglitz has been particularly influential.[citation needed]

Shirking

In the Shapiro-Stiglitz model workers are paid at a level where they do not shirk. This prevents wages from dropping to market-clearing levels. Full employment cannot be achieved because workers would shirk if they were not threatened with the possibility of unemployment. The curve for the no-shirking condition (labeled NSC) goes to infinity at full employment.

A theory in which employers voluntarily pay employees above the market equilibrium level to increase worker productivity. The shirking model begins with the fact that complete contracts rarely (or never) exist in the real world. This implies that both parties to the contract have some discretion, but frequently, due to monitoring problems, the employee's side of the bargain is subject to the most discretion. Methods such as piece rates are often impracticable because monitoring is too costly or inaccurate; or they may be based on measures too imperfectly verifiable by workers, creating a moral hazard problem on the employer's side. Thus, paying a wage in excess of market-clearing may provide employees with cost-effective incentives to work rather than shirk.[4][5]

In the Shapiro and Stiglitz model, workers either work or shirk, and if they shirk they have a certain probability of being caught, with the penalty of being fired.[6] Equilibrium then entails unemployment, because to create an opportunity cost to shirking, firms try to raise their wages above the market average (so that sacked workers face a probabilistic loss). But since all firms do this, the market wage itself is pushed up, and the result is that wages are raised above market-clearing, creating involuntary unemployment.[6] This creates a low, or no income alternative, which makes job loss costly and serves as a worker discipline device. Unemployed workers cannot bid for jobs by offering to work at lower wages since, if hired, it would be in the worker's interest to shirk on the job, and he has no credible way of promising not to do so. Shapiro and Stiglitz point out that their assumption that workers are identical (e.g. there is no stigma to having been fired)[6] is a strong one – in practice, reputation can work as an additional disciplining device. Conversely, higher wages and unemployment increase the cost of finding a new job after being laid off. So in the shirking model, higher wages are also a monetary incentive.

Shapiro-Stiglitz's model holds that unemployment threatens workers, and the stronger the danger, the more willing workers are to work through correct behavior. This view illustrates the endogenous decision-making of workers in the labor market; that is, workers will be more inclined to work hard when faced with the threat of unemployment to avoid the risk of unemployment. In the labor market, many factors influence workers' behavior and supply. Among them, the threat of unemployment is an essential factor affecting workers' behavior and supply. When workers are at risk of losing their jobs, they tend to increase their productivity and efficiency by working harder, thus improving their chances of employment. This endogenous decision of behavior and supply can somewhat alleviate the unemployment problem in the labor market.

The shirking model does not predict that the bulk of the unemployed at any one time are those fired for shirking, because if the threat associated with being fired is effective, little or no shirking and sacking will occur. Instead, the unemployed will consist of a rotating pool of individuals who have quit for personal reasons, are new entrants to the labour market, or have been laid off for other reasons. Pareto optimality, with costly monitoring, will entail some unemployment since unemployment plays a socially valuable role in creating work incentives. But the equilibrium unemployment rate will not be Pareto optimal since firms do not consider the social cost of the unemployment they helped to create.

One criticism of the efficiency wage hypothesis is that more sophisticated employment contracts can, under certain conditions, reduce or eliminate involuntary unemployment. The use of seniority wages to solve the incentive problem, where initially, workers are paid less than their marginal productivity, and as they work effectively over time within the firm, earnings increase until they exceed marginal productivity.[7] The upward tilt in the age-earnings profile here provides the incentive to avoid shirking, and the present value of wages can fall to the market-clearing level, eliminating involuntary unemployment. The slope of earnings profiles is significantly affected by incentives.[8]

However, a significant criticism is that moral hazard would be shifted to employers responsible for monitoring the worker's efforts. Employers do not want employees to be lazy. Employers want employees to be able to do more work while getting their reserved wages.[9] Obvious incentives would exist for firms to declare shirking when it has not taken place. In the Lazear model, firms have apparent incentives to fire older workers (paid above marginal product) and hire new cheaper workers, creating a credibility problem. The seriousness of this employer moral hazard depends on how much effort can be monitored by outside auditors, so that firms cannot cheat. However, reputation effects (e.g. Lazear 1981) may be able to do the same job.

Labor turnover

"Labor turnover" refers to rapid changes in the workforce from one position to another. This is determined by the ratio of the size of the labor and the number of employees employed.[10] With regards to the efficiency wage hypothesis, firms also offer wages in excess of market-clearing, due to the high cost of replacing workers (search, recruitment, training costs).[11][12][13][14] If all firms are identical, one possible equilibrium involves all firms paying a common wage rate above the market-clearing level, with involuntary unemployment serving to diminish turnover. These models can easily be adapted to explain dual labor markets: if low-skill, labor-intensive firms have lower turnover costs (as seems likely), there may be a split between a low-wage, low-effort, high-turnover sector and a high-wage, high effort, low-turnover sector. Again, more sophisticated employment contracts may solve the problem.

Selection

Similar to the shirking model, the selection model also believes that the information asymmetry problem is the main culprit that causes the market function not fully to exert to eliminate involuntary unemployment. However, unlike the shirking model, which focuses on employee shirking, the election model emphasizes the information disadvantage of employers in terms of labor quality. Due to the inability to accurately observe the real quality of employees, we only know that high wages can hire high-quality employees, and wage cuts will make high-quality employees go first. Therefore, wages will not continue to fall due to involuntary unemployment to maintain the excellent quality of workers.[citation needed]

In selection wage theories it is presupposed that performance on the job depends on "ability", and that workers are heterogeneous concerning ability. The selection effect of higher wages may come about through self-selection or because firms with a larger pool of applicants can increase their hiring standards and obtain a more productive workforce. Workers with higher abilities are more likely to earn more wages, and companies are willing to pay higher wages to hire high-quality people as employees.[citation needed]

Self-selection (often referred to as adverse selection) comes about if the workers’ ability and reservation wages are positively correlated.[15] The basic assumption of efficiency wage theory is that the efficiency of workers increases with the increase of wages. In this case, companies face a trade-off between hiring productive workers at higher salaries or less effective workers at lower wages. These notes derive the so-called Solow condition, which minimizes wages even if the cost of practical labor input is minimized. Solow condition means that in the labor market, the wage level paid by enterprises should equal the marginal product of workers, namely the market value of labor force. This condition is based on two basic assumptions: that firms operate in a competitive market and cannot control market wages and that individual workers are price takers rather than price setters. If there are two kinds of firms (low and high wage), then we effectively have two sets of lotteries (since firms cannot screen), the difference being that high-ability workers do not enter the low-wage lotteries as their reservation wage is too high. Thus low-wage firms attract only low-ability lottery entrants, while high-wage firms attract workers of all abilities (i.e. on average, they will select average workers). Therefore high-wage firms are paying an efficiency wage – they pay more and, on average, get more.[16] However, the assumption that firms cannot measure effort and pay piece rates after workers are hired or to fire workers whose output is too low is quite strong. Firms may also be able to design self-selection or screening devices that induce workers to reveal their true characteristics.[citation needed]

High wages can effectively reduce personnel turnover, promote employees to work harder, prevent employees from resigning collectively, and effectively attract more high-quality employees.[17] If firms can assess the productivity of applicants, they will try to select the best among the applicants. A higher wage offer will attract more applicants, particularly more highly qualified ones. This permits a firm to raise its hiring standard, thereby enhancing its productivity.[18] Wage compression makes it profitable for firms to screen applicants under such circumstances, and selection wages may be necessary.

Sociological models

Fairness, norms, and reciprocity

Standard economic models ("neoclassical economics") assume that people pursue only their self-interest and do not care about "social" goals ("homo economicus"). Neoclassical economics is divided into three theories, namely methodological individualism, methodological instrumentalist, and methodological equilibration.[19] Some attention has been paid to the idea that people may be altruistic, but it is only with the addition of reciprocity and norms of fairness that the model becomes accurate.[20] Thus of crucial importance is the idea of exchange: a person who is altruistic towards another expects the other to fulfil some fairness norm, be it reciprocating in kind, in some different but – according to some shared standard – equivalent way, or simply by being grateful. If the expected reciprocation is not forthcoming, the altruism will unlikely be repeated or continued. In addition, similar norms of fairness will typically lead people into negative forms of reciprocity, too – in retaliation for acts perceived as vindictive. This can bind actors into vicious loops where vindictive acts are met with further vindictive acts.

In practice, despite the neat logic of standard neoclassical models, these sociological models do impinge upon many economic relations, though in different ways and to different degrees. For example, suppose an employee has been exceptionally loyal. In that case, a manager may feel some obligation to treat that employee well, even when it is not in his (narrowly defined, economic) self-interest. It would appear that although broader, longer-term economic benefits may result (e.g. through reputation, or perhaps through simplified decision-making according to fairness norms), a significant factor must be that there are noneconomic benefits the manager receives, such as not having a guilty conscience (loss of self-esteem). For real-world, socialised, normal human beings (as opposed to abstracted factors of production), this is likely to be the case quite often. As a quantitative estimate of the importance of this, the total value of voluntary labor in the US – $74 billion annually – will suffice.[21] Examples of the negative aspect of fairness include consumers "boycotting" firms they disapprove of by not buying products they otherwise would (and therefore settling for second-best); and employees sabotaging firms they feel hard done by.

Rabin (1993) offers three stylised facts as a starting point on how norms affect behaviour: (a) people are prepared to sacrifice their material well-being to help those who are being kind; (b) they are also prepared to do this to punish those being unkind; (c) both (a) and (b) have a greater effect on behaviour as the material cost of sacrificing (in relative rather than absolute terms) becomes smaller. Rabin supports his Fact A by Dawes and Thaler's (1988) survey of the experimental literature, which concludes that for most one-shot public good decisions in which the individually optimal contribution is close to 0%, the contribution rate ranges from 40 to 60% of the socially optimal level. Fact B is demonstrated by the "ultimatum game" (e.g. Thaler 1988), where an amount of money is split between two people, one proposing a division, the other accepting or rejecting (where rejection means both get nothing). Rationally, the proposer should offer no more than a penny, and the decider accept any offer of at least a penny. Still, in practice, even in one-shot settings, proposers make fair proposals, and deciders are prepared to punish unfair offers by rejecting them. Fact C is tested and partially confirmed by Gerald Leventhal and David Anderson (1970), but is also reasonably intuitive. In the ultimatum game, a 90% split (regarded as unfair) is (intuitively) far more likely to be punished if the amount to be split is $1 than $1 million.

A crucial point (as noted in Akerlof 1982) is that notions of fairness depend on the status quo and other reference points. Experiments (Fehr and Schmidt 2000) and surveys (Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler 1986) indicate that people have clear notions of fairness based on particular reference points (disagreements can arise in the choice of reference point). Thus, for example, firms who raise prices or lower wages to take advantage of increased demand or increased labour supply are frequently perceived as acting unfairly, where the same changes are deemed acceptable when the firm makes them due to increased costs (Kahneman et al.). In other words, in people's intuitive "naïve accounting" (Rabin 1993), a key role is played by the idea of entitlements embodied in reference points (although as Dufwenberg and Kirchsteiger 2000 point out, there may be informational problems, e.g. for workers in determining what the firm's profit is, given tax avoidance and stock-price considerations). In particular, it is perceived as unfair for actors to increase their share at the expense of others. However, over time such a change may become entrenched and form a new reference point which (typically) is no longer in itself deemed unfair.

Sociological efficiency wage models

Solow (1981) argued that wage rigidity may be partly due to social conventions and principles of appropriate behaviour, which are not entirely individualistic.[22] Akerlof (1982) provided the first explicitly sociological model leading to the efficiency wage hypothesis. Using a variety of evidence from sociological studies, Akerlof argues that worker effort depends on the work norms of the relevant reference group. In Akerlof's partial gift exchange model, the firm can raise group work norms and average effort by paying workers a gift of wages over the minimum required in return for effort above the minimum required. The sociological model can explain phenomena inexplicable on neoclassical terms, such as why firms do not fire workers who turn out to be less productive, why piece rates are so little used even where quite feasible; and why firms set work standards exceeded by most workers. A possible criticism is that workers do not necessarily view high wages as gifts, but as merely fair (particularly since typically 80% or more of workers consider themselves in the top quarter of productivity), in which case they will not reciprocate with high effort.

Akerlof and Yellen (1990), responding to these criticisms and building on work from psychology, sociology, and personnel management, introduce "the fair wage-effort hypothesis", which states that workers form a notion of the fair wage, and if the actual wage is lower, withdraw effort in proportion, so that, depending on the wage-effort elasticity and the costs to the firm of shirking, the fair wage may form a key part of the wage bargain. This explains persistent evidence of consistent wage differentials across industries (e.g. Slichter 1950; Dickens and Katz 1986; Krueger and Summers 1988): if firms must pay high wages to some groups of workers – perhaps because they are in short supply or for other efficiency-wage reasons such as shirking – then demands for fairness will lead to a compression of the pay scale, and wages for different groups within the firm will be higher than in other industries or firms.

The union threat model is one of several explanations for industry wage differentials.[23] This Keynesian economics model looks at the role of unions in wage determination. The degree in which union wages exceed non-union member wages is known as union wage premium. Some firms seek to prevent unionization in the first instances.[23] Varying costs of union avoidance across sectors will lead some firms to offer supracompetitive wages as pay premiums to workers in exchange for their avoiding unionization.[23] Under the union threat model (Dickens 1986), the ease with which industry can defeat a union drive has a negative relationship with its wage differential.[23] In other words, inter-industry wage variability should be low where the threat of unionization is low.[23]

Empirical literature

Raff and Summers (1987) conduct a case study on Henry Ford’s introduction of the five dollar day in 1914. Their conclusion is that the Ford experience supports efficiency wage interpretations. Ford’s decision to increase wages so dramatically (doubling for most workers) is most plausibly portrayed as the consequence of efficiency wage considerations, with the structure being consistent, evidence of substantial queues for Ford jobs, and significant increases in productivity and profits at Ford. Concerns such as high turnover and poor worker morale appear to have played an important role in the five-dollar decision. Ford’s new wage put him in the position of rationing jobs, and increased wages did yield substantial productivity benefits and profits. There is also evidence that other firms emulated Ford’s policy to some extent, with wages in the automobile industry 40% higher than in the rest of manufacturing (Rae 1965, quoted in Raff and Summers). Given low monitoring costs and skill levels on the Ford production line, such benefits (and the decision itself) appear particularly significant.

Fehr, Kirchler, Weichbold and Gächter (1998) conduct labour market experiments to separate the effects of competition and social norms/customs/standards of fairness. They find that firms persistently try to enforce lower wages in complete contract markets. By contrast, wages are higher and more stable in gift exchange markets and bilateral gift exchanges. It appears that in complete contract situations, competitive equilibrium exerts a considerable drawing power, whilst in the gift exchange market it does not.

Fehr et al. stress that reciprocal effort choices are truly a one-shot phenomenon without reputation or other repeated-game effects. "It is, therefore, tempting to interpret reciprocal effort behavior as a preference phenomenon."(p344). Two types of preferences can account for this behaviour: a) workers may feel obligated to share the additional income from higher wages at least partly with firms; b) workers may have reciprocal motives (reward good behaviour, punish bad). "In the context of this interpretation, wage setting is inherently associated with signaling intentions, and workers condition their effort responses on the inferred intentions." (p344). Charness (1996), quoted in Fehr et al., finds that when signaling is removed (wages are set randomly or by the experimenter), workers exhibit a lower, but still positive, wage-effort relation, suggesting some gain-sharing motive and some reciprocity (where intentions can be signaled).

Fehr et al. state that "Our preferred interpretation of firms’ wage-setting behavior is that firms voluntarily paid job rents to elicit non-minimum effort levels." Although excess supply of labour created enormous competition among workers, firms did not take advantage. In the long run, instead of being governed by competitive forces, firms’ wage offers were solely governed by reciprocity considerations because the payment of non-competitive wages generated higher profits. Thus, firms and workers can be better off relying on stable reciprocal interactions. That is to say, when the demands of enterprises and workers reach a balance point, it is stable and developing for both parties.

That reciprocal behavior generates efficiency gains has been confirmed by several other papers e.g. Berg, Dickhaut, and McCabe (1995) – even under conditions of double anonymity and where actors know even the experimenter cannot observe individual behaviour, reciprocal interactions, and efficiency gains are frequent. Fehr, Gächter, and Kirchsteiger (1996, 1997) show that reciprocal interactions generate substantial efficiency gains. However, the efficiency-enhancing role of reciprocity is generally associated with serious behavioural deviations from competitive equilibrium predictions. To counter a possible criticism of such theories, Fehr and Tougareva (1995) showed these reciprocal exchanges (efficiency-enhancing) are independent of the stakes involved (they compared outcomes with stakes worth a week's income with stakes worth 3 months’ income and found no difference).

As one counter to over-enthusiasm for efficiency wage models, Leonard (1987) finds little support for shirking or turnover efficiency wage models, by testing their predictions for large and persistent wage differentials. The shirking version assumes a trade-off between self-supervision and external supervision, while the turnover version assumes turnover is costly to the firm. Variation in the cost of monitoring/shirking or turnover is hypothesized to account for wage variations across firms for homogeneous workers. But Leonard finds that wages for narrowly defined occupations within one sector of one state are widely dispersed, suggesting other factors may be at work. Efficiency wage models do not explain everything about wages. For example, involuntary unemployment and persistent wage rigidity are often problematic in many economies. But the efficiency wage model fails to account for these issues.[24]

Mathematical explanation

Paul Krugman explains how the efficiency wage theory comes into play in real society. The productivity [math]\displaystyle{ E(w) }[/math] of individual workers is a function of their wage [math]\displaystyle{ w }[/math], and the total productivity is the sum of individual productivity.[25] Accordingly, the sales [math]\displaystyle{ V }[/math] of the firm to which the workers belong becomes a function of both employment [math]\displaystyle{ L }[/math] and the individual productivity. The firm's profit [math]\displaystyle{ P }[/math] is[25]

[math]\displaystyle{ P = V(LE) - w L \; . }[/math]

Then we assume that the higher the wage of the workers become, the higher the individual productivity: [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{d E }{d w} \gt 0 }[/math].[25] If the employment is chosen so that the profit is maximised, it is constant. Under this optimised condition, we have

[math]\displaystyle{ dP = \frac{\partial V}{\partial (LE)} d E - L d w \; , }[/math]

that is,

[math]\displaystyle{ \frac{dP}{dw} = \frac{\partial V}{\partial E} \frac{d E}{d w} - L \; . }[/math]

Obviously, the gradient [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{\partial V}{\partial E} }[/math] of the slope is positive, because the higher individual productivity the higher sales. The [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{d P}{d w} }[/math] never goes to negative because of the optimised condition, and therefore we have

[math]\displaystyle{ 0 \leq \frac{d P}{d w} \; . }[/math]

This means that if the firm increases their wage their profit becomes constant or even larger. Because after the employee's salary increases, the employee will work harder, and will not easily quit or go to other companies. This increases the stability of the company and the motivation of employees. Thus the efficiency wage theory motivates the owners of the firm to raise the wage to increase the profit of the firm, and high wages can also be called a reward mechanism.

Limitations of efficiency wage theory

  • Morale: While wages can affect morale, there are other factors, such as working conditions and management, that can also affect the overall mood of employees.[citation needed]
  • Competitors: If competing organizations also raise wages, the benefits of attracting highly skilled candidates are reduced because they have more employment options.[citation needed]
  • Monopoly: If there is only one buyer in a particular market, then increasing wages may have little or no effect on the organization's ability to increase employee stress.[citation needed]

Notes

  1. 1.0 1.1 1.2 Marshall, Alfred (1920). "Earnings of Labour Book VI Chapter III". Principles of Economics (8th ed.). London: Macmillan and Co., Ltd.. doi:10.1057/9781137375261_45. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137375261_45. 
  2. 2.0 2.1 Mankiw, Gregory N. & Taylor, Mark P. (2008), Macroeconomics (European edition), pp. 181–182
  3. Garibaldi, Pietro; Oliveira Martins, Joaquim; van Ours, Jan (2010-11-25). Ageing, Health, and Productivity. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199587131.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-958713-1. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199587131.001.0001. 
  4. Becker, Gary S.; Stigler, George J. (January 1974). "Law Enforcement, Malfeasance, and Compensation of Enforcers". The Journal of Legal Studies 3 (1): 6–16. doi:10.1086/467507. https://www.jstor.org/stable/724119. 
  5. Gintis, Herbert (1976). "The Nature of Labor Exchange and the Theory of Capitalist Production". Review of Radical Political Economics 8 (2): 36–54. doi:10.1177/048661347600800203. http://www.umass.edu/preferen/gintis/gintis%20labor%20exchange%20rrpe%201976.pdf. 
  6. 6.0 6.1 6.2 Shapiro, Carl; Stiglitz, Joseph E. (June 1984). "Equilibrium Unemployment as a Worker Discipline Device". The American Economic Review 74 (3): 433–444. https://www.jstor.org/stable/1804018. 
  7. Lazear (1979, 1981)
  8. Lazear and Moore (1984)
  9. Weiss, A. (2008). "Efficiency Wages". The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. London: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 1–4. doi:10.1057/978-1-349-95121-5_2144-1. ISBN 978-1-349-95121-5. 
  10. Douglas, Paul H. (1918). "The Problem of Labor Turnover". The American Economic Review 8 (2): 306–316. ISSN 0002-8282. https://www.jstor.org/stable/1811123. 
  11. Phelps, Edmund S. (1968). "Money-Wage Dynamics and Labor-Market Equilibrium". Journal of Political Economy 76 (4): 678–711. doi:10.1086/259438. 
  12. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (1974). "Alternative Theories of Wage Determination and Unemployment in LDC's: The Labor Turnover Model". The Quarterly Journal of Economics 88 (2): 194–227. doi:10.2307/1883069. 
  13. Schlicht, Ekkehart (1978). "Labour Turnover, Wages Structure, and Natural Unemployment". Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 134 (2): 337–346. https://epub.ub.uni-muenchen.de/1255/1/schlicht_labour_turnover-EP.pdf. 
  14. Salop, Steven C. (1979). "A Model of the Natural Rate of Unemployment". The American Economic Review 69 (1): 117–125. https://www.jstor.org/stable/1802502. 
  15. Weiss, Andrew (1980). "Job Queues and Layoffs in Labor Markets with Flexible Wages". Journal of Political Economy 88 (3): 526–538. doi:10.1086/260884. https://www.jstor.org/stable/1831930. 
  16. see e.g. Malcolmson 1981; Stiglitz 1976; Weiss 1980
  17. Katz, Lawrence F. (January 1986). "Efficiency Wage Theories: A Partial Evaluation". NBER Macroeconomics Annual 1: 235–276. doi:10.1086/654025. ISSN 0889-3365. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/654025. 
  18. Schlicht, Ekkehart (2005). "Hiring Standards and Labour Market Clearing". Metroeconomica 56 (2): 263–279. doi:10.1111/j.1467-999X.2005.00216.x. 
  19. Arnsperger, Christian; Varoufakis, Yanis (2008), "Neoclassical Economics Three Identifying Features", Pluralist Economics (Zed Books), doi:10.5040/9781350221772.ch-001, ISBN 978-1-84813-044-9, http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781350221772.ch-001, retrieved 2022-05-02 
  20. e.g. Rabin 1993; Dufwenberg and Kirchsteiger 2000; Fehr and Schmidt 2000
  21. Weisbrod's 1988
  22. McDonald, Ian M.; Solow, Robert M (December 1981). "Wage Bargaining and Employment". American Economic Review 71 (5): 896–908. https://bf060be7-a-62cb3a1a-s-sites.googlegroups.com/site/intromacroeconomielille1/le-travail/McDonaldSolowWageBargainingandEmployment.pdf?attachauth=ANoY7crvCafQ7lPlCJDgC2S66tZNwefXGchPUjzdMO_SAsnjk6c9NcAgbfmAyiCO2vTN8V6OpcMfyG9Cw_K2NJAHcZ-0FJEHQQU0Oab12XucW_H8zXAgEAWQOmlPX0JW_vw0t7D3PPS9BlW7klNNbH6RUgfFB9nW1NhZpFy8yim_igiqAI_xGxbvZujJEUqgO99L-S0AjBakrZhJyimXRRXbZAFPqmtvuae9xetL9gnk9oOYZsanZSJDgIznDFriy8dc6ysImS5fYigJ0GIBNttmqHq869o-IvidNe0GJLrqWCGNbJNsl9I%3D&attredirects=0. Retrieved 25 March 2013. 
  23. 23.0 23.1 23.2 23.3 23.4 Mankiw. N. Gregory (Editor); Romer, David (Editor). (April 24, 1991) New Keynesian Economics, Vol. 2: Coordination Failures and Real Rigidities. Page 161. Publisher: MIT Press. ISBN:0-262-63134-2
  24. Carmichael, H. LORNE (April 1990). "Efficiency Wage Models of Unemployment-One View". Economic Inquiry 28 (2): 269–295. doi:10.1111/j.1465-7295.1990.tb00816.x. ISSN 0095-2583. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1465-7295.1990.tb00816.x. 
  25. 25.0 25.1 25.2 Krugman, P. (10 June 2015). "Notes on Walmart and Wages (Wonkish)". The Conscience of a Liberal (The New York Times). https://krugman.blogs.nytimes.com/2015/06/10/notes-on-walmart-and-wages-wonkish/. 

References