Philosophy:Destructive dilemma
Type | Rule of inference |
---|---|
Field | Propositional calculus |
Statement | If [math]\displaystyle{ P }[/math] implies [math]\displaystyle{ Q }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ R }[/math] implies [math]\displaystyle{ S }[/math] and either [math]\displaystyle{ Q }[/math] is false or [math]\displaystyle{ S }[/math] is false, then either [math]\displaystyle{ P }[/math] or [math]\displaystyle{ R }[/math] must be false. |
Transformation rules |
---|
Propositional calculus |
Rules of inference |
Rules of replacement |
Predicate logic |
Destructive dilemma[1][2] is the name of a valid rule of inference of propositional logic. It is the inference that, if P implies Q and R implies S and either Q is false or S is false, then either P or R must be false. In sum, if two conditionals are true, but one of their consequents is false, then one of their antecedents has to be false. Destructive dilemma is the disjunctive version of modus tollens. The disjunctive version of modus ponens is the constructive dilemma. The destructive dilemma rule can be stated:
- [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{P \to Q, R \to S, \neg Q \lor \neg S}{\therefore \neg P \lor \neg R} }[/math]
where the rule is that wherever instances of "[math]\displaystyle{ P \to Q }[/math]", "[math]\displaystyle{ R \to S }[/math]", and "[math]\displaystyle{ \neg Q \lor \neg S }[/math]" appear on lines of a proof, "[math]\displaystyle{ \neg P \lor \neg R }[/math]" can be placed on a subsequent line.
Formal notation
The destructive dilemma rule may be written in sequent notation:
- [math]\displaystyle{ (P \to Q), (R \to S), (\neg Q \lor \neg S) \vdash (\neg P \lor \neg R) }[/math]
where [math]\displaystyle{ \vdash }[/math] is a metalogical symbol meaning that [math]\displaystyle{ \neg P \lor \neg R }[/math] is a syntactic consequence of [math]\displaystyle{ P \to Q }[/math], [math]\displaystyle{ R \to S }[/math], and [math]\displaystyle{ \neg Q \lor \neg S }[/math] in some logical system;
and expressed as a truth-functional tautology or theorem of propositional logic:
- [math]\displaystyle{ (((P \to Q) \land (R \to S)) \land (\neg Q \lor \neg S)) \to (\neg P \lor \neg R) }[/math]
where [math]\displaystyle{ P }[/math], [math]\displaystyle{ Q }[/math], [math]\displaystyle{ R }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ S }[/math] are propositions expressed in some formal system.
Natural language example
- If it rains, we will stay inside.
- If it is sunny, we will go for a walk.
- Either we will not stay inside, or we will not go for a walk, or both.
- Therefore, either it will not rain, or it will not be sunny, or both.
Proof
Step | Proposition | Derivation |
---|---|---|
1 | [math]\displaystyle{ P \to Q }[/math] | Given |
2 | [math]\displaystyle{ R \to S }[/math] | Given |
3 | [math]\displaystyle{ \neg Q \lor \neg S }[/math] | Given |
4 | [math]\displaystyle{ \neg Q \to \neg P }[/math] | Transposition (1) |
5 | [math]\displaystyle{ \neg S \to \neg R }[/math] | Transposition (2) |
6 | [math]\displaystyle{ (\neg Q \to \neg P) \land (\neg S \to \neg R) }[/math] | Conjunction introduction (4,5) |
7 | [math]\displaystyle{ \neg P \lor \neg R }[/math] | Constructive dilemma (6,3) |
Example proof
The validity of this argument structure can be shown by using both conditional proof (CP) and reductio ad absurdum (RAA) in the following way:
1. | [math]\displaystyle{ ((P \rightarrow Q) \And (R \rightarrow S)) \And (\neg Q \vee \neg S) }[/math] | (CP assumption) |
2. | [math]\displaystyle{ (P \rightarrow Q) \And (R \rightarrow S) }[/math] | (1: simplification) |
3. | [math]\displaystyle{ (P \rightarrow Q) }[/math] | (2: simplification) |
4. | [math]\displaystyle{ (R \rightarrow S) }[/math] | (2: simplification) |
5. | [math]\displaystyle{ (\neg Q \vee \neg S) }[/math] | (1: simplification) |
6. | [math]\displaystyle{ \neg (\neg P \vee \neg R) }[/math] | (RAA assumption) |
7. | [math]\displaystyle{ \neg \neg P \And \neg \neg R }[/math] | (6: De Morgan's Law) |
8. | [math]\displaystyle{ \neg \neg P }[/math] | (7: simplification) |
9. | [math]\displaystyle{ \neg \neg R }[/math] | (7: simplification) |
10. | [math]\displaystyle{ P }[/math] | (8: double negation) |
11. | [math]\displaystyle{ R }[/math] | (9: double negation) |
12. | [math]\displaystyle{ Q }[/math] | (3,10: modus ponens) |
13. | [math]\displaystyle{ S }[/math] | (4,11: modus ponens) |
14. | [math]\displaystyle{ \neg \neg Q }[/math] | (12: double negation) |
15. | [math]\displaystyle{ \neg S }[/math] | (5, 14: disjunctive syllogism) |
16. | [math]\displaystyle{ S \And \neg S }[/math] | (13,15: conjunction) |
17. | [math]\displaystyle{ \neg P \vee \neg R }[/math] | (6-16: RAA) |
18. | [math]\displaystyle{ (((P \rightarrow Q) \And (R \rightarrow S)) \And (\neg Q \vee \neg S))) \rightarrow \neg P \vee \neg R }[/math] | (1-17: CP) |
References
Bibliography
- Howard-Snyder, Frances; Howard-Snyder, Daniel; Wasserman, Ryan. The Power of Logic (4th ed.). McGraw-Hill, 2009, ISBN:978-0-07-340737-1, p. 414.
External links
Original source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Destructive dilemma.
Read more |