Social:Efficient envy-free division

From HandWiki

Efficiency and fairness are two major goals of welfare economics. Given a set of resources and a set of agents, the goal is to divide the resources among the agents in a way that is both Pareto efficient (PE) and envy-free (EF). The goal was first defined by David Schmeidler and Menahem Yaari.[1] Later, the existence of such allocations has been proved under various conditions.

Existence of PEEF allocations

We assume that each agent has a preference-relation on the set of all bundles of commodities. The preferences are complete, transitive, and closed. Equivalently, each preference relation can be represented by a continuous utility function.[2]:79

Weakly-convex preferences

Theorem 1 (Varian):[2]:68 If the preferences of all agents are convex and strongly monotone, then PEEF allocations exist.

Proof: The proof relies on the existence of a competitive equilibrium with equal incomes. Assume that all resources in an economy are divided equally between the agents. I.e, if the total endowment of the economy is [math]\displaystyle{ E }[/math], then each agent [math]\displaystyle{ i\in 1,\dots,n: }[/math] receives an initial endowment [math]\displaystyle{ E_i = E/n }[/math].

Since the preferences are convex, the Arrow–Debreu model implies that a competitive equilibrium exists. I.e, there is a price vector [math]\displaystyle{ P }[/math] and a partition [math]\displaystyle{ X }[/math] such that:

  • (CE) All agents maximize their utilities given their budget. I.e, if [math]\displaystyle{ P\cdot Y \leq P\cdot X_i }[/math] then [math]\displaystyle{ Y \preceq_i X_i }[/math].
  • (EI) All agents have the same income in the equilibrium prices: for all [math]\displaystyle{ i,j: P\cdot X_i = P\cdot X_j }[/math].

Such an allocation is always EF. Proof: by the (EI) condition, for every [math]\displaystyle{ i,j: P\cdot X_j \leq P\cdot X_i }[/math]. Hence, by the (CE) condition, [math]\displaystyle{ X_j \preceq_i X_i }[/math].

Since the preferences are monotonic, any such allocation is also PE, since monotonicity implies local nonsatiation. See fundamental theorems of welfare economics.

Examples

All examples involve an economy with two goods, x and y, and two agents, Alice and Bob. In all examples, the utilities are weakly-convex and continuous.

A. Many PEEF allocations: The total endowment is (4,4). Alice and Bob have linear utilities, representing substitute goods:

[math]\displaystyle{ u_A(x,y)=2x+y }[/math],
[math]\displaystyle{ u_B(x,y)=x+2y }[/math].

Note that the utilities are weakly-convex and strongly-monotone. Many PEEF allocations exist. If Alice receives at least 3 units of x, then her utility is 6 and she does not envy Bob. Similarly, if Bob receives at least 3 units of y, he does not envy Alice. So the allocation [(3,0);(1,4)] is PEEF with utilities (6,9). Similarly, the allocations [(4,0);(0,4)] and [(4,0.5);(0,3.5)] are PEEF. On the other hand, the allocation [(0,0);(4,4)] is PE but not EF (Alice envies Bob); the allocation [(2,2);(2,2)] is EF but not PE (the utilities are (6,6) but they can be improved e.g. to (8,8)).

B. Essentially-single PEEF allocation: The total endowment is (4,2). Alice and Bob have Leontief utilities, representing complementary goods:

[math]\displaystyle{ u_A(x,y)=u_B(x,y)=\min(x,y) }[/math].

Note that the utilities are weakly-convex and only weakly-monotone. Still A PEEF allocation exists. The equal allocation [(2,1);(2,1)] is PEEF with utility vector (1,1). EF is obvious (every equal allocation is EF). Regarding PE, note that both agents now want only y, so the only way to increase the utility of an agent is to take some y from the other agent, but this decreases the utility of the other agent. While there are other PEEF allocations, e.g. [(1.5,1);(2.5,1)], all have the same utility vector of (1,1), since it is not possible to give both agents more than 1.[3]

Topological conditions on the space of efficient allocations

PEEF allocations exist even when agents' preferences are not convex. There are several sufficient conditions that are related to the shape of the set of allocations corresponding to a specific efficient utility profile. Given a utility-vector u, define A(u) = the set of all allocations for which the utility-profile is u. The following successively more general theorems were proved by different authors:

Theorem 2 (Varian):[2]:69 Suppose all agents' preferences are strongly monotone. If, for every Weakly Pareto Efficient utility-profile u, the set A(u) is a singleton (i.e, there are no two WPE allocations such that all agents are indifferent between them), then PEEF allocations exist.

The proof uses the Knaster–Kuratowski–Mazurkiewicz lemma.

Note: The conditions in Theorem 1 and in Theorem 2 are independent - none of them implies the other. However, strict-convexity of preferences implies both of them. It is obvious that strict-convexity implies weak-convexity (theorem 1). To see that it implies the condition of theorem 2, suppose there are two different allocations x,y with the same utility profile u. Define z = x/2+y/2. By strict convexity, all agents strictly prefer z to x and to y. Hence, x and y cannot be weakly-PE.

Theorem 3 (Svensson):[4] If all agents' preferences are strongly monotone, and for every PE utility-profile u, the set A(u) is convex, then PEEF allocations exist.

The proof uses the Kakutani fixed-point theorem.

Note: if all agents' preferences are convex (as in theorem 1), then A(u) is obviously convex too. Moreover, if A(u) is singleton (as in theorem 2) then it is obviously convex too. Hence, Svensson's theorem is more general than both Varian's theorems.

Theorem 4 (Diamantaras):[5] If all agents' preferences are strongly monotone, and for every PE utility-profile u, the set A(u) is a contractible space (can be continuously shrunk to a point within that space), then PEEF allocations exist.

The proof uses a fixed-point theorem by Eilenberg and Montgomery.[6]

Note: Every convex set is contractible, so Diamantaras' theorem is more general than the previous three.

Sigma-optimality

Svensson proved another sufficient condition for the existence of PEEF allocations. Again all preferences are represented by continuous utility functions. Moreover, all utility functions are continuously differentiable in the interior of the consumption space.

The main concept is sigma-optimality. Suppose we create, for each agent, k copies with identical preferences. Let X be an allocation in the original economy. Let Xk be an allocation in the k-replicated economy where all copies of the same agent receive the same bundle as the original agent in X. The allocation X is called sigma-optimal if for every k, the allocation Xk is Pareto-optimal.

Lemma:[7]:528 An allocation is sigma-optimal, if-and-only-if it is a competitive equilibrium.

Theorem 5 (Svensson):[7]:531 if all Pareto-optimal allocations are sigma-optimal, then PEEF allocations exist.

Increasing marginal returns

PEEF allocations might fail to exist even when all preferences are convex, if there is production and the technology has increasing-marginal-returns.

Proposition 6 (Vohra):[8] There exist economies in which all preferences are continuous strongly-monotone and convex, the only source of non-convexity in the technology is due to fixed costs, and there exists no PEEF allocation.

Thus, the presence of increasing returns introduces a fundamental conflict between efficiency and fairness.

However, envy-freeness can be weakened in the following way. An allocation X is defined as essentially envy-free (EEF) if, for every agent i, there is a feasible allocation Yi with the same utility profile (all agents are indifferent between X and Yi) in which agent i does not envy anyone. Obviously, every EF allocation is EEF, since we can take Yi to be X for all i.

Theorem 7 (Vohra):[8] Suppose all agents' preferences are strongly monotone, and represented by continuous utility functions. Then, Pareto-efficient EEF allocations exist.

Non-existence of PEEF allocations

Non-convex preferences

PEEF allocations might fail to exist even without production, when the preferences are non-convex.

As an example, suppose the total endowment is (4,2), and Alice and Bob have identical concave utilities:

[math]\displaystyle{ u_A(x,y)=u_B(x,y)=\max(x,y) }[/math].

The equal allocation [(2,1);(2,1)] is EF with utility vector (2,2). Moreover, every EF allocation must give both agents equal utility (since they have the same utility function) and this utility can be at most 2. However, no such allocation is PE, since it is Pareto-dominated by the allocation [(4,0);(0,2)] whose utility vector is (4,2).

Non-existence remains even if we weaken envy-freeness to no domination -- no agent gets more of each good than another agent.

Proposition 8 (Maniquet):[9] There exist 2-good 3-agent division economies with strictly monotonic, continuous and even differentiable preferences, where there is domination at every Pareto efficient allocation.

Finding a PEEF allocation

For two agents, the adjusted winner procedure is a simple procedure that finds a PEEF allocation with two additional properties: the allocation is also equitable, and at most a single good is shared between the two agents.

For three or more agents with linear utilities, any Nash-optimal allocation is PEEF. A Nash-optimal allocation is an allocation that maximizes the product of the utilities of the agents, or equivalently, the sum of logarithms of utilities. Finding such an allocation is a convex optimization problem:

[math]\displaystyle{ \text{maximize} \sum_{i=1}^n \log(u_i(X_i)) ~~~\text{such that}~~~ (X_1,\ldots,X_n) ~~~\text{is a partition}~~~ }[/math].

and thus it can be found efficiently. The fact that any Nash-optimal allocation is PEEF is true even in the more general setting of fair cake-cutting.[10]

Proof: Consider an infinitesimal piece of cake, Z. For each agent i, the infinitesimal contribution of Z to [math]\displaystyle{ \log(u_i(X_i)) }[/math]is

[math]\displaystyle{ u_i(Z)\cdot {d \log(u_i(X_i))\over d (u_i(X_i))} = {u_i(Z) \over u_i(X_i)} }[/math].

Therefore, the Nash-optimal rule gives each such piece Z to an agent j for which this expression is largest:


[math]\displaystyle{ \forall j\in[n]: Z\subseteq X_j \iff \forall i\in[n]: {u_j(Z)\over u_j(X_j)} \geq {u_i(Z)\over u_i(X_i)} }[/math]

Summing over all infinitesimal subsets of Xj, we get:

[math]\displaystyle{ \forall i,j\in[n]: {u_j(X_j )\over u_j(X_j )} \geq {u_i(X_j)\over u_i(X_i)} }[/math]

This implies the definition of envy-free allocation:

[math]\displaystyle{ \forall i,j\in[n]: {u_i(X_i)} \geq {u_i(X_j)} }[/math]

See also

  • Weller's theorem - on the existence of PEEF allocations in cake-cutting.
  • More related theorems by Hal Varian can be found in.[11]
  • Theorems about PEEF allocations in economies with production can be found in.[12]
  • Market equilibrium computation - algorithms for computing a competitive equilibrium, which is both fair and efficient.
  • Tao and Cole[13] study the existence of PEEF random allocations when the utilities are non-linear (can have complements).
  • Diamantaras and Thomson[14] study a refinement and extension of envy-freeness, which exists (together with PE) in many economies in which a PEEF allocation does not exist.

References

  1. David Schmeidler and Menahem Yaari (1971). "Fair allocations". Mimeo.
  2. 2.0 2.1 2.2 Hal Varian (1974). "Equity, envy, and efficiency". Journal of Economic Theory 9: 63–91. doi:10.1016/0022-0531(74)90075-1. 
  3. Note that a similar economy appears in the 1974 paper:70 as an example that a PEEF allocation does not exist. This is probably a typo - the "min" should be "max", as in example C below. See this economics stack-exchange thread.
  4. Svensson, Lars-Gunnar (1983-09-01). "On the existence of fair allocations" (in en). Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie 43 (3): 301–308. doi:10.1007/BF01283577. ISSN 0044-3158. 
  5. Diamantaras, Dimitrios (1992-06-01). "On equity with public goods" (in en). Social Choice and Welfare 9 (2): 141–157. doi:10.1007/BF00187239. ISSN 0176-1714. 
  6. Eilenberg, Samuel; Montgomery, Deane (1946). "Fixed Point Theorems for Multi-Valued Transformations". American Journal of Mathematics 68 (2): 214–222. doi:10.2307/2371832. 
  7. 7.0 7.1 Svensson, Lars-Gunnar (1994). "σ-Optimality and Fairness". International Economic Review 35 (2): 527–531. doi:10.2307/2527068. 
  8. 8.0 8.1 Vohra, Rajiv (1992-07-01). "Equity and efficiency in non-convex economies" (in en). Social Choice and Welfare 9 (3): 185–202. doi:10.1007/BF00192877. ISSN 0176-1714. 
  9. Maniquet, François (1999-12-01). "A strong incompatibility between efficiency and equity in non-convex economies" (in en). Journal of Mathematical Economics 32 (4): 467–474. doi:10.1016/S0304-4068(98)00067-6. ISSN 0304-4068. 
  10. Segal-Halevi, Erel; Sziklai, Balázs R. (2018-05-26). "Monotonicity and competitive equilibrium in cake-cutting" (in en). Economic Theory 68 (2): 363–401. doi:10.1007/s00199-018-1128-6. ISSN 1432-0479. 
  11. Varian, Hal R. (1976). "Two problems in the theory of fairness". Journal of Public Economics 5 (3–4): 249–260. doi:10.1016/0047-2727(76)90018-9. http://dspace.mit.edu/bitstream/1721.1/64180/1/twoproblemsinthe00vari.pdf. 
  12. Piketty, Thomas (1994-11-01). "Existence of fair allocations in economies with production" (in en). Journal of Public Economics 55 (3): 391–405. doi:10.1016/0047-2727(93)01406-Z. ISSN 0047-2727. 
  13. Cole, Richard; Tao, Yixin (2021-04-01). "On the existence of Pareto Efficient and envy-free allocations" (in en). Journal of Economic Theory 193: 105207. doi:10.1016/j.jet.2021.105207. ISSN 0022-0531. https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0022053121000247. 
  14. Diamantaras, Dimitrios; Thomson, William (1990-07-01). "A refinement and extension of the no-envy concept" (in en). Economics Letters 33 (3): 217–222. doi:10.1016/0165-1765(90)90004-K. ISSN 0165-1765. https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/abs/pii/016517659090004K.