Religion:Aseity

From HandWiki
Revision as of 18:19, 3 February 2024 by Carolyn (talk | contribs) (link)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Short description: Attribute of God in Christian theology

Aseity (from Latin a "from" and se "self", plus -ity) is the property by which a being exists of and from itself.[1] It refers to the Christian belief that God does not depend on any cause other than himself for his existence, realization, or end, and has within himself his own reason of existence. This represents God as absolutely independent and self-existent by nature. Many Jewish and Muslim theologians have also believed God to be independent in this way.[1] This quality of independence and self-existence has been affirmed under various names by theologians going back to antiquity, though the use of the word 'aseity' began only in the Middle Ages.[1]

Meaning

Aseity has two aspects, one positive and one negative: absolute independence and self-existence.[1] W. N. Clarke writes:

In its negative meaning, which emerged first in the history of thought, it [aseity] affirms that God is uncaused, depending on no other being for the source of His existence. In its positive meaning, it affirms that God is completely self-sufficient, having within Himself the sufficient reason for His own existence.[2]

The first concept derives from "the God of philosophers" (a concept first described by Xenophanes),[3] while the second one derives from "the living God of Revelation" (I Am Who I Am: Exodus 3:14).[4]

As a part of this belief, an aseitous God is said to be incapable of changing (see Hebrews 13:8)[1] Changing implies development. Since God was, and is, and is to be the Absolute Perfection, there is no need to change: he is αὐτουσία (unchanged: Gregory of Nyssa),[5][6] actus purus[7] and ipsum esse subsistens[8][9] (Thomas Aquinas).

Many (Thomas Aquinas, for instance) have also thought that aseity implies divine simplicity: that God has no parts of any kind (whether spatial, temporal, or abstract), since complexes depend on their individual parts, with none of which they are identical.[10] Classical theists have often drawn a further implication: that God is without emotion or is "impassible": because, it is said, emotion implies standing as patient (pass-) to some agent – i.e., dependence.[11] This is so because, although God has created everything, he is not in dependence on his creation.

Philosophical considerations

Whether this being should be described as God turns on whether the label 'Creator' is a rigid designator of God. Given that most theists believe all that is not God to be brought about by God, and that many (for example, St. Aquinas) argue from the non-aseity of the universe to the existence of God, this problem is highly theoretical. There is also a possible threat to divine aseity by the existence of abstract objects, a threat that philosopher William Lane Craig attempts to provide reconciliations for in his book, God Over All. John 1:3 states that "All things came into being through him, and without him not one thing came into being". The aorist tense implies that everything that exists (other than God) came into being at some time in the past. This verse carries the weighty metaphysical implication that there are no eternal entities apart from God, eternal either in the sense of existing atemporally or of existing sempiternally. Rather everything that exists, with the exception of God Himself, is the product of temporal becoming.[12]

Aseity has also been criticized as logically incompatible with the concept of God as a being or with God as existing.[13] Furthermore, it can be argued that for the notion of aseity not to be logically circular or inconsistent, the supposed entity to which it applies would have to be identified with its properties, instead of instantiating, exemplifying or having its properties, and would therefore be a nonsentient force or potential of indeterminate vitality (see monad). This seems to contradict the notion that God is a person or a causal agent, for persons or agents are not properties (or complexes of properties).[14] Schopenhauer attributes Aseity (self-dependent) to will, as the only being by and of itself, apart from causal relationships.[15]

See also


References

  1. 1.0 1.1 1.2 1.3 1.4 Sauvage, George (1907). "Aseity". Catholic Encyclopedia, New Advent. http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/01774b.htm. 
  2. Clarke, W. N. (January 1, 2003). "Aseity (Aseitas)". New Catholic Encyclopedia. http://www.highbeam.com/doc/1G2-3407700842.html. "Aseity has two aspects, one positive and one negative. In its negative meaning, which emerged first in the history of thought, it affirms that God is uncaused, depending on no other being for the source of God's existence. In its positive meaning, it affirms that God is completely self-sufficient, having within Godself the sufficient reason for God's own existence." 
  3. "The Reception of Xenophanes’ Philosophical Theology in Plato and the Christian Platonists". https://www.prometheustrust.co.uk/The_Reception_of_Xenophanes_Philosophical_Theology_in_Plato_and_the_Christian_Platonists_--_Monika_Recinova.pdf. 
  4. Jean Daniélou (1957). "The God Of True Philosophy". God and the Ways of Knowing. San Francisco: Ignatius Press. pp. 210. ISBN 978-0898709391. http://webcache.googleusercontent.com/search?q=cache:rICaQzU6q8IJ:payingattentiontothesky.com/2012/02/16/the-god-of-true-philosophy-by-jean-danielou/+aseity+%22Ego%20sum%20qui%20sum%22&cd=1&hl=en. Retrieved July 15, 2012. .
  5. Pohle, Joseph (1911). Dogmatic Theology, Vol. 1: God, His Knowability, Essence, and Attributes. Freiburg im Breisgau: B. Herder. ISBN 978-1440052811. https://books.google.com/books?id=0M2y5Ar-6F8C.  pp. 162, 172, 174.
  6. See also occurrences.
  7. Pohle (1911). P. 164.
  8. Pohle (1911). Ibid..
  9. See also occurrences.
  10. Summa Theologica, I, Q. 3, Art. 7.
  11. For an exposition of Augustine's theory of emotions, especially with respect to God's perfection, see Nicholas Wolterstorff's "Suffering Love" in Philosophy and the Christian Faith, ed. Thomas V. Morris (Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, 1988).
  12. Craig, William Lane. "Biblical Basis of God's Unique Aseity". http://www.reasonablefaith.org/biblical-basis-of-gods-unique-aseity. 
  13. Paul Tillich, Systematic Theology (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1951) 236ff.
  14. Richard M. Gale, On the Nature and Existence of God
  15. Payne, E. "The World as Will and Representation" (Vol.2) Dover. 1958, p. 320

Bibliography

  • Alston, William P. "Hartshorne and Aquinas: A Via Media", in Divine Nature and Human Language. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1989.
  • Hartshorne, Charles. The Divine Relativity: A Social Conception of God. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1948.
  • Morris, Thomas V. Our Idea of God. Chap. 6. Downer's Grove, Illinois: InterVarsity Press, 1991.
  • Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologica, I, Q. 3. Many editions.

External links