Apportionment paradox

From HandWiki
Short description: Political system apportionment phenomenon

An apportionment paradox exists when the rules for apportionment in a political system produce results which are unexpected or seem to violate common sense.

To apportion is to divide into parts according to some rule, the rule typically being one of proportion. Certain quantities, like milk, can be divided in any proportion whatsoever; others, such as horses, cannot—only whole numbers will do. In the latter case, there is an inherent tension between the desire to obey the rule of proportion as closely as possible and the constraint restricting the size of each portion to discrete values. This results, at times, in unintuitive observations, or paradoxes.

Several paradoxes related to apportionment, also called fair division, have been identified. In some cases, simple post facto adjustments, if allowed, to an apportionment methodology can resolve observed paradoxes. However, as shown by examples relating to the United States House of Representatives, and subsequently proven by the Balinski–Young theorem, mathematics alone cannot always provide a single, fair resolution to the apportionment of remaining fractions into discrete equal whole-number parts, while complying fully with all the competing fairness elements.[1]:227–235

History

An example of the apportionment paradox known as "the Alabama paradox" was discovered in the context of United States congressional apportionment in 1880,[1]:228–231 when census calculations found that if the total number of seats in the House of Representatives were hypothetically increased, this would decrease Alabama's seats from 8 to 7. An actual impact was observed in 1900, when Virginia lost a seat to Maine, even though Virginia's population was growing more rapidly: this is an example of the population paradox.[1]:231–232 In 1907, when Oklahoma became a state, New York lost a seat to Maine, thus the name "the new state paradox".[1]:232–233[2]

The method for apportionment used during this period, originally put forth by Alexander Hamilton, but vetoed by George Washington and not adopted until 1852,[1]:228 was as follows:

  • First, the fair share of each state is computed, i.e. the proportional share of seats that each state would get if fractional values were allowed.
  • Second, each state receives as many seats as the whole number portion of its fair share.
  • Third, any state whose fair share is less than one receives one seat, regardless of population, as required by the United States Constitution.
  • Fourth, any remaining seats are distributed, one each, to the states whose fair shares have the highest fractional parts.

The Hamilton method replaced a rounding method proposed by Thomas Jefferson,[1]:228 and was itself replaced by the Huntington–Hill method in 1941.[1]:233 Under certain conditions, the Huntington-Hill method can also give paradoxical results.[citation needed]

Examples of paradoxes

Alabama paradox

The Alabama paradox was the first of the apportionment paradoxes to be discovered. The US House of Representatives is constitutionally required to allocate seats based on population counts, which are required every 10 years. The size of the House is set by statute.

After the 1880 census, C. W. Seaton, chief clerk of the United States Census Bureau, computed apportionments for all House sizes between 275 and 350, and discovered that Alabama would get eight seats with a House size of 299 but only seven with a House size of 300.[1]:228–231 In general the term Alabama paradox refers to any apportionment scenario where increasing the total number of items would decrease one of the shares. A similar exercise by the Census Bureau after the 1900 census computed apportionments for all House sizes between 350 and 400: Colorado would have received three seats in all cases, except with a House size of 357 in which case it would have received two.[3]

The following is a simplified example (following the largest remainder method) with three states and 10 seats and 11 seats.

With 10 seats With 11 seats
State Population Fair share Seats Fair share Seats
A 6 4.286 4 4.714 5
B 6 4.286 4 4.714 5
C 2 1.429 2 1.571 1

Observe that state C's share decreases from 2 to 1 with the added seat.

In this example of a 10% increase in the number of seats, each state's share increases by 10%. However, increasing the number of seats by a fixed % increases the fair share more for larger numbers (i.e., large states more than small states). In particular, large A and B had their fair share increase faster than small C. Therefore, the fractional parts for A and B increased faster than those for C. In fact, they overtook C's fraction, causing C to lose its seat, since the Hamilton method allocates according to which states have the largest fractional remainder.

The Alabama paradox gave rise to the axiom known as house monotonicity, which says that, when the house size increases, the allocations of all states should weakly increase.

Population paradox

The population paradox is a counterintuitive result of some procedures for apportionment. When two states have populations increasing at different rates, a small state with rapid growth can lose a legislative seat to a big state with slower growth.

Some of the earlier Congressional apportionment methods, such as Hamilton, could exhibit the population paradox. In 1900, Virginia lost a seat to Maine, even though Virginia's population was growing more rapidly.[1]:231–232 However, divisor methods such as the current method do not.[4]

New states paradox

Given a fixed number of total representatives (as determined by the United States House of Representatives), adding a new state would in theory reduce the number of representatives for existing states, as under the United States Constitution each state is entitled to at least one representative regardless of its population. Also, even if the number of members in the House of Representatives is increased by the number of Representatives in the new state, a pre-existing state could lose a seat because of how the particular apportionment rules deal with rounding methods. In 1907, when Oklahoma became a state, it was given a fair share of seats and the total number of seats increased by that number. The House increased from 386 to 391 members. A recomputation of apportionment affected the number of seats because of other states: New York lost a seat while Maine gained one.[1]:232–233[2]

The Alabama paradox gave rise to the axiom known as coherence, which says that, whenever an apportionment rule is activated on a subset of the states, with the subset of seats allocated to them, the outcome should be the same as in the grand solution.

Balinski–Young theorem

In 1983, two mathematicians, Michel Balinski and Peyton Young, proved that any method of apportionment that does not violate the quota rule will result in paradoxes whenever there are four or more parties (or states, regions, etc.).[5][6] More precisely, their theorem states that there is no apportionment system that has the following properties for more than four states[1]:233–234 (as the example we take the division of seats between parties in a system of proportional representation):

  • It avoids violations of the quota rule: Each of the parties gets one of the two numbers closest to its fair share of seats. For example, if a party's fair share is 7.34 seats, it must get either 7 or 8 seats to avoid a violation; any other number will violate the rule.
  • It does not have the Alabama paradox: If the total number of seats is increased, no party's number of seats decreases.
  • It does not have the population paradox: If party A gets more votes and party B gets fewer votes, no seat will be transferred from A to B.

It is of note that any method of apportionment free of the Population Paradox will always be free of Alabama Paradox. The converse is not true, however.

Interestingly, Webster's method can be free of the Population Paradox and the Alabama Paradox and not violate quota when there are three or fewer states. All divisor methods (which is exactly the class of all apportionment methods that are free of the population paradox) do not violate the quota rule for two states.[5][6]

They show a proof of impossibility: apportionment methods may have a subset of these properties, but cannot have all of them:

  • A method may follow quota and be free of the Alabama paradox. Balinski and Young constructed a method that does so, although it is not in common political use.[7]
  • A method may be free of both the Alabama paradox and the population paradox. These methods are divisor methods,[4] and Huntington-Hill, the method currently used to apportion House of Representatives seats, is one of them. However, these methods will necessarily fail to always follow quota in other circumstances.
  • No method may always follow quota and be free of the population paradox.[4][8]
public static long[] BalinskiYoung(long quantity, double[] weights)
{
    var sumWeights = weights.Sum();
    var allocations = new long[weights.Length];
    for (var q = 1L; q <= quantity; q++)
    {
        var rmax = double.MinValue;
        var amin = long.MaxValue;
        var index = -1;
        for (int i = 0; i < weights.Length; i++)
        {
            var a = allocations[i];
            var w = weights[i];
            if (a < w * q / sumWeights) // to keep to quota rule
            {
                var r = w / (1 + a); // divisor method
                if (r > rmax || (r == rmax && a < amin))
                {
                    rmax = r;
                    amin = a;
                    index = i;
                }
            }
        }
        allocations[index]++;
    }
    return allocations;
}

The division of seats in an election is a prominent cultural concern. In 1876, the United States presidential election turned on the method by which the remaining fraction was calculated. Rutherford Hayes received 185 electoral college votes, and Samuel Tilden received 184. Tilden won the popular vote. With a different rounding method the final electoral college tally would have reversed.[1]:228 However, many mathematically analogous situations arise in which quantities are to be divided into discrete equal chunks.[1]:233 The Balinski–Young theorem applies in these situations: it indicates that although very reasonable approximations can be made, there is no mathematically rigorous way to reconcile the small remaining fraction while complying with all the competing fairness elements.[1]:233

References

  1. 1.00 1.01 1.02 1.03 1.04 1.05 1.06 1.07 1.08 1.09 1.10 1.11 1.12 1.13 Stein, James D. (2008). How Math Explains the World: A Guide to the Power of Numbers, from Car Repair to Modern Physics. New York: Smithsonian Books. ISBN 9780061241765. 
  2. 2.0 2.1 Caulfield, Michael J. (November 2010). "Apportioning Representatives in the United States Congress - Paradoxes of Apportionment". Convergence (Mathematical Association of America). doi:10.4169/loci003163. http://www.maa.org/publications/periodicals/convergence/apportioning-representatives-in-the-united-states-congress-paradoxes-of-apportionment. 
  3. Bogomolny, Alex (January 2002). "The Constitution and Paradoxes". Cut The Knot!. http://www.cut-the-knot.org/ctk/Democracy.shtml. 
  4. 4.0 4.1 4.2 Smith, Warren D. (January 2007). "Apportionment and rounding schemes". RangeVoting.org. http://rangevoting.org/Apportion.html. 
  5. 5.0 5.1 Balinski, Michel L.; Young, H. Peyton (1982). Fair Representation: Meeting the Ideal of One Man, One Vote. New Haven: Yale University Press. ISBN 0-300-02724-9. https://archive.org/details/fairrepresentati00bali. 
  6. 6.0 6.1 Balinski, Michel L.; Young, H. Peyton (2001). Fair Representation: Meeting the Ideal of One Man, One Vote (2nd ed.). Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press. ISBN 0-8157-0111-X. 
  7. Balinski, Michel L.; Young, H. Peyton (November 1974). "A New Method for Congressional Apportionment". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 71 (11): 4602–4606. doi:10.1073/pnas.71.11.4602. PMID 16592200. Bibcode1974PNAS...71.4602B. 
  8. Balinski, Michel L.; Young, H. Peyton (September 1980). "The Theory of Apportionment". Working Papers. International Institute for Applied Systems Analysis. http://pure.iiasa.ac.at/id/eprint/1338/1/WP-80-131.pdf. 

External links