Solomonoff's theory of inductive inference

From HandWiki
Revision as of 18:05, 6 February 2024 by MedAI (talk | contribs) (link)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

Solomonoff's theory of inductive inference is a mathematical theory of induction introduced by Ray Solomonoff, based on probability theory and theoretical computer science.[1][2][3] In essence, Solomonoff's induction derives the posterior probability of any computable theory, given a sequence of observed data. This posterior probability is derived from Bayes' rule and some universal prior, that is, a prior that assigns a positive probability to any computable theory.

Solomonoff's induction naturally formalizes Occam's razor[4][5][6][7][8] by assigning larger prior credences to theories that require a shorter algorithmic description.

Origin

Philosophical

The theory is based in philosophical foundations, and was founded by Ray Solomonoff around 1960.[9] It is a mathematically formalized combination of Occam's razor[4][5][6][7][8] and the Principle of Multiple Explanations.[10] All computable theories which perfectly describe previous observations are used to calculate the probability of the next observation, with more weight put on the shorter computable theories. Marcus Hutter's universal artificial intelligence builds upon this to calculate the expected value of an action.

Principle

Solomonoff's induction has been argued to be the computational formalization of pure Bayesianism.[3] To understand, recall that Bayesianism derives the posterior probability [math]\displaystyle{ \mathbb P[T|D] }[/math] of a theory [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] given data [math]\displaystyle{ D }[/math] by applying Bayes rule, which yields [math]\displaystyle{ \mathbb P[T|D] = \mathbb P[D|T] \mathbb P[T] / (\mathbb P[D|T] \mathbb P[T] + \sum_{A \neq T} \mathbb P[D|A] \mathbb P[A]) }[/math], where theories [math]\displaystyle{ A }[/math] are alternatives to theory [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math]. For this equation to make sense, the quantities [math]\displaystyle{ \mathbb P[D|T] }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ \mathbb P[D|A] }[/math] must be well-defined for all theories [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ A }[/math]. In other words, any theory must define a probability distribution over observable data [math]\displaystyle{ D }[/math]. Solomonoff's induction essentially boils down to demanding that all such probability distributions be computable.

Interestingly, the set of computable probability distributions is a subset of the set of all programs, which is countable. Similarly, the sets of observable data considered by Solomonoff were finite. Without loss of generality, we can thus consider that any observable data is a finite bit string. As a result, Solomonoff's induction can be defined by only invoking discrete probability distributions.

Solomonoff's induction then allows to make probabilistic predictions of future data [math]\displaystyle{ F }[/math], by simply obeying the laws of probability. Namely, we have [math]\displaystyle{ \mathbb P[F|D] = \mathbb E_T [\mathbb P[F|T,D] ] = \sum_T \mathbb P[F|T,D] \mathbb P[T|D] }[/math]. This quantity can be interpreted as the average predictions [math]\displaystyle{ \mathbb P[F|T,D] }[/math] of all theories [math]\displaystyle{ T }[/math] given past data [math]\displaystyle{ D }[/math], weighted by their posterior credences [math]\displaystyle{ \mathbb P[T|D] }[/math].

Mathematical

The proof of the "razor" is based on the known mathematical properties of a probability distribution over a countable set. These properties are relevant because the infinite set of all programs is a denumerable set. The sum S of the probabilities of all programs must be exactly equal to one (as per the definition of probability) thus the probabilities must roughly decrease as we enumerate the infinite set of all programs, otherwise S will be strictly greater than one. To be more precise, for every [math]\displaystyle{ \epsilon }[/math] > 0, there is some length l such that the probability of all programs longer than l is at most [math]\displaystyle{ \epsilon }[/math]. This does not, however, preclude very long programs from having very high probability.

Fundamental ingredients of the theory are the concepts of algorithmic probability and Kolmogorov complexity. The universal prior probability of any prefix p of a computable sequence x is the sum of the probabilities of all programs (for a universal computer) that compute something starting with p. Given some p and any computable but unknown probability distribution from which x is sampled, the universal prior and Bayes' theorem can be used to predict the yet unseen parts of x in optimal fashion.

Mathematical guarantees

Solomonoff's completeness

The remarkable property of Solomonoff's induction is its completeness. In essence, the completeness theorem guarantees that the expected cumulative errors made by the predictions based on Solomonoff's induction are upper-bounded by the Kolmogorov complexity of the (stochastic) data generating process. The errors can be measured using the Kullback–Leibler divergence or the square of the difference between the induction's prediction and the probability assigned by the (stochastic) data generating process.

Solomonoff's uncomputability

Unfortunately, Solomonoff also proved that Solomonoff's induction is uncomputable. In fact, he showed that computability and completeness are mutually exclusive: any complete theory must be uncomputable. The proof of this is derived from a game between the induction and the environment. Essentially, any computable induction can be tricked by a computable environment, by choosing the computable environment that negates the computable induction's prediction. This fact can be regarded as an instance of the no free lunch theorem.

Modern applications

Artificial intelligence

Though Solomonoff's inductive inference is not computable, several AIXI-derived algorithms approximate it in order to make it run on a modern computer. The more computing power they are given, the closer their predictions are to the predictions of inductive inference (their mathematical limit is Solomonoff's inductive inference).[11][12][13]

Another direction of inductive inference is based on E. Mark Gold's model of learning in the limit from 1967 and has developed since then more and more models of learning.[14] The general scenario is the following: Given a class S of computable functions, is there a learner (that is, recursive functional) which for any input of the form (f(0),f(1),...,f(n)) outputs a hypothesis (an index e with respect to a previously agreed on acceptable numbering of all computable functions; the indexed function may be required consistent with the given values of f). A learner M learns a function f if almost all its hypotheses are the same index e, which generates the function f; M learns S if M learns every f in S. Basic results are that all recursively enumerable classes of functions are learnable while the class REC of all computable functions is not learnable.[citation needed] Many related models have been considered and also the learning of classes of recursively enumerable sets from positive data is a topic studied from Gold's pioneering paper in 1967 onwards. A far reaching extension of the Gold’s approach is developed by Schmidhuber's theory of generalized Kolmogorov complexities,[15] which are kinds of super-recursive algorithms.

Turing machines

The third mathematically based direction of inductive inference makes use of the theory of automata and computation. In this context, the process of inductive inference is performed by an abstract automaton called an inductive Turing machine (Burgin, 2005). Inductive Turing machines represent the next step in the development of computer science providing better models for contemporary computers and computer networks (Burgin, 2001) and forming an important class of super-recursive algorithms as they satisfy all conditions in the definition of algorithm. Namely, each inductive Turing machine is a type of effective method in which a definite list of well-defined instructions for completing a task, when given an initial state, will proceed through a well-defined series of successive states, eventually terminating in an end-state. The difference between an inductive Turing machine and a Turing machine is that to produce the result a Turing machine has to stop, while in some cases an inductive Turing machine can do this without stopping. Stephen Kleene called procedures that could run forever without stopping by the name calculation procedure or algorithm (Kleene 1952:137). Kleene also demanded that such an algorithm must eventually exhibit "some object" (Kleene 1952:137). This condition is satisfied by inductive Turing machines, as their results are exhibited after a finite number of steps, but inductive Turing machines do not always tell at which step the result has been obtained.

Simple inductive Turing machines are equivalent to other models of computation. More advanced inductive Turing machines are much more powerful. It is proved (Burgin, 2005) that limiting partial recursive functions, trial and error predicates, general Turing machines, and simple inductive Turing machines are equivalent models of computation. However, simple inductive Turing machines and general Turing machines give direct constructions of computing automata, which are thoroughly grounded in physical machines. In contrast, trial and error predicates, limiting recursive functions and limiting partial recursive functions present syntactic systems of symbols with formal rules for their manipulation. Simple inductive Turing machines and general Turing machines are related to limiting partial recursive functions and trial and error predicates as Turing machines are related to partial recursive functions and lambda-calculus.

Note that only simple inductive Turing machines have the same structure (but different functioning semantics of the output mode) as Turing machines. Other types of inductive Turing machines have an essentially more advanced structure due to the structured memory and more powerful instructions. Their utilization for inference and learning allows achieving higher efficiency and better reflects learning of people (Burgin and Klinger, 2004).

Some researchers confuse computations of inductive Turing machines with non-stopping computations or with infinite time computations. First, some computations of inductive Turing machines halt. As in the case of conventional Turing machines, some halting computations give the result, while others do not give. Second, some non-stopping computations of inductive Turing machines give results, while others do not give. Rules of inductive Turing machines determine when a computation (stopping or non-stopping) gives a result. Namely, an inductive Turing machine produces output from time to time and once this output stops changing, it is considered the result of the computation. It is necessary to know that descriptions of this rule in some papers are incorrect. For instance, Davis (2006: 128) formulates the rule when result is obtained without stopping as "once the correct output has been produced any subsequent output will simply repeat this correct result." Third, in contrast to the widespread misconception, inductive Turing machines give results (when it happens) always after a finite number of steps (in finite time) in contrast to infinite and infinite-time computations. There are two main distinctions between conventional Turing machines and simple inductive Turing machines. The first distinction is that even simple inductive Turing machines can do much more than conventional Turing machines. The second distinction is that a conventional Turing machine always informs (by halting or by coming to a final state) when the result is obtained, while a simple inductive Turing machine in some cases does inform about reaching the result, while in other cases (where the conventional Turing machine is helpless), it does not inform. People have an illusion that a computer always itself informs (by halting or by other means) when the result is obtained. In contrast to this, users themselves have to decide in many cases whether the computed result is what they need or it is necessary to continue computations. Indeed, everyday desktop computer applications like word processors and spreadsheets spend most of their time waiting in event loops, and do not terminate until directed to do so by users.

Evolutionary inductive Turing machines

Evolutionary approach to inductive inference is accomplished by another class of automata called evolutionary inductive Turing machines (Burgin and Eberbach, 2009; 2012). An evolutionary inductive Turing machine is a (possibly infinite) sequence E = {A[t]; t = 1, 2, 3, ... } of inductive Turing machines A[t] each working on generations X[t] which are coded as words in the alphabet of the machines A[t]. The goal is to build a “population” Z satisfying the inference condition. The automaton A[t] called a component, or a level automaton, of E represents (encodes) a one-level evolutionary algorithm that works with input generations X[i] of the population by applying the variation operators v and selection operator s. The first generation X[0] is given as input to E and is processed by the automaton A[1], which generates/produces the first generation X[1] as its transfer output, which goes to the automaton A[2]. For all t = 1, 2, 3, ..., the automaton A[t] receives the generation X[t − 1] as its input from A[t − 1] and then applies the variation operator v and selection operator s, producing the generation X[i + 1] and sending it to A[t + 1] to continue evolution.

See also

References

  1. Zenil, Hector (2011-02-11) (in en). Randomness Through Computation: Some Answers, More Questions. World Scientific. ISBN 978-981-4462-63-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=ep_FCgAAQBAJ&q=Algorithmic+Probability+--+Its+Discovery+--+Its+Properties+and+Application+to+Strong+AI&pg=PA149. 
  2. Solomonoff, Ray J. (2009), Emmert-Streib, Frank; Dehmer, Matthias, eds., "Algorithmic Probability: Theory and Applications" (in en), Information Theory and Statistical Learning (Boston, MA: Springer US): pp. 1–23, doi:10.1007/978-0-387-84816-7_1, ISBN 978-0-387-84816-7, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-0-387-84816-7_1, retrieved 2020-07-21 
  3. 3.0 3.1 Hoang, Lê Nguyên (2020). The equation of knowledge : from Bayes' rule to a unified philosophy of science (First ed.). Boca Raton, FL. ISBN 978-0-367-85530-7. OCLC 1162366056. https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/1162366056. 
  4. 4.0 4.1 JJ McCall. Induction: From Kolmogorov and Solomonoff to De Finetti and Back to Kolmogorov – Metroeconomica, 2004 – Wiley Online Library.
  5. 5.0 5.1 D Stork. Foundations of Occam's razor and parsimony in learning from ricoh.com – NIPS 2001 Workshop, 2001
  6. 6.0 6.1 A.N. Soklakov. Occam's razor as a formal basis for a physical theory from arxiv.org – Foundations of Physics Letters, 2002 – Springer
  7. 7.0 7.1 Jose Hernandez-Orallo (1999). "Beyond the Turing Test". Journal of Logic, Language and Information 9. http://users.dsic.upv.es/proy/anynt/Beyond.pdf. 
  8. 8.0 8.1 M Hutter. On the existence and convergence of computable universal priors arxiv.org – Algorithmic Learning Theory, 2003 – Springer
  9. Samuel Rathmanner and Marcus Hutter. A philosophical treatise of universal induction. Entropy, 13(6):1076–1136, 2011
  10. Ming Li and Paul Vitanyi, An Introduction to Kolmogorov Complexity and Its Applications. Springer-Verlag, N.Y., 2008p 339 ff.
  11. J. Veness, K.S. Ng, M. Hutter, W. Uther, D. Silver. "A Monte Carlo AIXI Approximation" – Arxiv preprint, 2009 arxiv.org
  12. J. Veness, K.S. Ng, M. Hutter, D. Silver. "Reinforcement Learning via AIXI Approximation" Arxiv preprint, 2010 – aaai.org
  13. S. Pankov. A computational approximation to the AIXI model from agiri.org – Artificial general intelligence, 2008: proceedings of …, 2008 – books.google.com
  14. Gold, E. Mark (1967). "Language identification in the limit". Information and Control 10 (5): 447–474. doi:10.1016/S0019-9958(67)91165-5. http://web.mit.edu/~6.863/www/spring2009/readings/gold67limit.pdf. 
  15. J. Schmidhuber (2002). "Hierarchies of generalized Kolmogorov complexities and nonenumerable universal measures computable in the limit". International Journal of Foundations of Computer Science 13 (4): 587–612. doi:10.1142/S0129054102001291. ftp://ftp.idsia.ch/pub/juergen/ijfcspreprint.pdf. 

Sources

  • Angluin, Dana; Smith, Carl H. (Sep 1983). "Inductive Inference: Theory and Methods". Computing Surveys 15 (3): 237–269. doi:10.1145/356914.356918. https://dl.acm.org/doi/pdf/10.1145/356914.356918. 
  • Burgin, M. (2005), Super-recursive Algorithms, Monographs in computer science, Springer. ISBN:0-387-95569-0
  • Burgin, M., "How We Know What Technology Can Do", Communications of the ACM, v. 44, No. 11, 2001, pp. 82–88.
  • Burgin, M.; Eberbach, E., "Universality for Turing Machines, Inductive Turing Machines and Evolutionary Algorithms", Fundamenta Informaticae, v. 91, No. 1, 2009, 53–77.
  • Burgin, M.; Eberbach, E., "On Foundations of Evolutionary Computation: An Evolutionary Automata Approach", in Handbook of Research on Artificial Immune Systems and Natural Computing: Applying Complex Adaptive Technologies (Hongwei Mo, Ed.), IGI Global, Hershey, Pennsylvania, 2009, 342–360.
  • Burgin, M.; Eberbach, E., "Evolutionary Automata: Expressiveness and Convergence of Evolutionary Computation", Computer Journal, v. 55, No. 9, 2012, pp. 1023–1029.
  • Burgin, M.; Klinger, A. Experience, Generations, and Limits in Machine Learning, Theoretical Computer Science, v. 317, No. 1/3, 2004, pp. 71–91
  • Davis, Martin (2006) "The Church–Turing Thesis: Consensus and opposition]". Proceedings, Computability in Europe 2006. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 3988 pp. 125–132.
  • Gasarch, W.; Smith, C. H. (1997) "A survey of inductive inference with an emphasis on queries". Complexity, logic, and recursion theory, Lecture Notes in Pure and Appl. Math., 187, Dekker, New York, pp. 225–260.
  • Hay, Nick. "Universal Semimeasures: An Introduction," CDMTCS Research Report Series, University of Auckland, Feb. 2007.
  • Jain, Sanjay; Osherson, Daniel; Royer, James; Sharma, Arun, Systems that Learn: An Introduction to Learning Theory (second edition), MIT Press, 1999.
  • Kleene, Stephen C. (1952), Introduction to Metamathematics (First ed.), Amsterdam: North-Holland .
  • Li Ming; Vitanyi, Paul, An Introduction to Kolmogorov Complexity and Its Applications, 2nd Edition, Springer Verlag, 1997.
  • Osherson, Daniel; Stob, Michael; Weinstein, Scott, Systems That Learn, An Introduction to Learning Theory for Cognitive and Computer Scientists, MIT Press, 1986.
  • Solomonoff, Ray J. (1999). "Two Kinds of Probabilistic Induction". The Computer Journal 42 (4): 256. doi:10.1093/comjnl/42.4.256. http://world.std.com/~rjs/compj99.pdf. 
  • Solomonoff, Ray (March 1964). "A Formal Theory of Inductive Inference Part I". Information and Control 7 (1): 1–22. doi:10.1016/S0019-9958(64)90223-2. http://world.std.com/~rjs/1964pt1.pdf. 
  • Solomonoff, Ray (June 1964). "A Formal Theory of Inductive Inference Part II". Information and Control 7 (2): 224–254. doi:10.1016/S0019-9958(64)90131-7. http://world.std.com/~rjs/1964pt2.pdf. 

External links