Biography:Frank P. Ramsey

From HandWiki
Frank P. Ramsey
Frank Plumpton Ramsey.JPG
Born(1903-02-22)22 February 1903
Cambridge
Died19 January 1930(1930-01-19) (aged 26)
EducationTrinity College, Cambridge (BA, 1923)
Era20th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolAnalytic philosophy
InstitutionsKing's College, Cambridge
Main interests
Philosophy of mathematics
Logic
Metaphysics
Epistemology
Notable ideas
Redundancy theory of truth
Ramsey sentences
Ramsey–Lewis method
Ramsey theory

Frank Plumpton Ramsey (/ˈræmzi/; 22 February 1903 – 19 January 1930) was a British philosopher, mathematician, and economist who made major contributions to all three fields before his death at the age of 26. He was a close friend of Ludwig Wittgenstein and was instrumental in translating Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus into English, as well as persuading Wittgenstein to return to philosophy and Cambridge. Like Wittgenstein, he was a member of the Cambridge Apostles, the intellectual secret society, from 1921.

Life

Ramsey was born on 22 February 1903 in Cambridge where his father Arthur Stanley Ramsey (1867–1954), also a mathematician, was President of Magdalene College. His mother was Mary Agnes Stanley (1875–1927). He was the eldest of two brothers and two sisters, and his brother Michael Ramsey, the only one of the four siblings who was to remain Christian, later became Archbishop of Canterbury. He entered Winchester College in 1915 and later returned to Cambridge to study mathematics at Trinity College. There he became a student of John Maynard Keynes, and an active member in the Apostles. In 1923, he received his bachelor's degree in mathematics, passing his examinations with the result of first class with distinction, and was named Senior Wrangler (top of his class).[2] Easy-going, simple and modest, Ramsey had many interests besides his mathematical and scientific studies. Even as a teenager Ramsey exhibited both a profound ability and, as attested by his brother, an extremely diverse range of interests:

He was interested in almost everything. He was immensely widely read in English literature; he was enjoying classics though he was on the verge of plunging into being a mathematical specialist; he was very interested in politics, and well-informed; he had got a political concern and a sort of left-wing caring-for-the-underdog kind of outlook about politics.

Michael Ramsey, Quoted in Mellor

In 1923, Ramsey was befriended by Geoffrey and Margaret Pyke, then on the point of founding the Malting House School in Cambridge; the Pykes took Ramsey into their family, taking him on holiday and asking him to be the godfather of their young son. Margaret found herself to be the object of his affection, Ramsey recording in his diary:

One afternoon I went out alone with her on Lake Orta and became filled with desire and we came back and lay on two beds side by side she reading, I pretending to, but with an awful conflict in my mind. After about an hour I said (she was wearing her horn spectacles and looking superlatively beautiful in the Burne Jones style) ‘Margaret will you fuck with me?’[3]

Margaret wanted time to consider his proposition and thus began an uncomfortable dance between them, which contributed to Ramsey's depressive moods in early 1924; as a result, he travelled to Vienna for psychoanalysis. Like many of his contemporaries, including his Viennese flatmate and fellow Apostle Lionel Penrose (also in analysis with Siegfried Bernfeld), Ramsey was intellectually interested in psychoanalysis. Ramsey's analyst was Theodor Reik, a disciple of Freud. As one of the justifications for undertaking the therapy, he asserted in a letter to his mother that unconscious impulses might even affect the work of a mathematician. While in Vienna, he made a trip to Puchberg in order to visit Wittgenstein, was befriended by the Wittgenstein family and visited A.S. Neill's experimental school four hours from Vienna at Sonntagsberg. In the summer of 1924, he continued his analysis by joining Reik at Dobbiaco (in South Tyrol), where a fellow analysand was Lewis Namier. Ramsey returned to England in October 1924; with John Maynard Keynes's support he became a fellow of King's College, Cambridge. He joined a Psychoanalysis Group in Cambridge with fellow members Arthur Tansley, Lionel Penrose, Harold Jeffreys, John Rickman and James Strachey, the qualification for membership of which was a completed psychoanalysis.

Ramsey married Lettice Baker in September 1925, the wedding taking place in a Register Office since Ramsey was, as his wife described him, a ‘militant atheist'. After Ramsey's death, Lettice Ramsey opened a photography studio in Cambridge with photographer Helen Muspratt.[4] The marriage produced two daughters. Despite his atheism, Ramsey was quite tolerant towards his brother when the latter decided to become a priest in the Church of England.[5]

In 1926 he became a university lecturer in mathematics and later a Director of Studies in Mathematics at King's College. The Vienna Circle manifesto (1929) lists three of his publications[6][7][8] in a bibliography of closely related authors.

Ramsey and Wittgenstein

When I. A. Richards and C. K. Ogden, both Fellows of Magdalene, first met Ramsey, he expressed his interest in learning German. According to Richards, he mastered the language "in almost hardly over a week",[9] although other sources show he had taken one year of German in school.[10] Ramsey was then able, at the age of 19, to make the first draft of the translation of the German text of Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico Philosophicus. Ramsey was impressed by Wittgenstein's work and after graduating as Senior Wrangler in the Mathematical Tripos of 1923 he made a journey to Austria to visit Wittgenstein, at that time teaching in a primary school in the small community of Puchberg am Schneeberg. For two weeks Ramsey discussed the difficulties he was facing in understanding the Tractatus. Wittgenstein made some corrections to the English translation in Ramsey's copy and some annotations and changes to the German text that subsequently appeared in the second edition in 1933.

Ramsey and John Maynard Keynes cooperated to try to bring Ludwig Wittgenstein back to Cambridge (he had been a student there before World War I). Once Wittgenstein had returned to Cambridge, Ramsey became his nominal supervisor. Wittgenstein submitted the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus as his doctoral thesis. G.E. Moore and Bertrand Russell acted as examiners. Later, the three of them arranged financial aid for Wittgenstein to help him continue his research work.

In 1929 Ramsey and Wittgenstein regularly discussed issues in mathematics and philosophy with Piero Sraffa, an Italian economist who had been brought to Cambridge by Keynes after Sraffa had aroused Benito Mussolini's ire by publishing an article critical of the Fascist regime in the Manchester Guardian. The contributions of Ramsey to these conversations were acknowledged by both Sraffa and Wittgenstein in their later work, the latter mentioning him in the introduction to his Philosophical Investigations as an influence.

Early death

Suffering from chronic liver problems, Ramsey developed jaundice after an abdominal operation and died on 19 January 1930 at Guy's Hospital in London at the age of 26.

He is buried in the Parish of the Ascension Burial Ground in Cambridge; his parents are buried in the same plot.[11]

Ramsey's notes and manuscripts were acquired by Nicholas Rescher for the Archives of Scientific Philosophy at the University of Pittsburgh. This collection contains only a few letters but a great many drafts of papers and book chapters, some still unpublished. Other papers, including his diary and letters and memoirs by his widow Lettice Ramsey and his father, are held in the Modern Archives, King's College, Cambridge.

Work

Mathematical logic

One of the theorems proved by Ramsey in his 1928 paper On a Problem of Formal Logic now bears his name (Ramsey's theorem). While this theorem is the work Ramsey is probably best remembered for, he only proved it in passing, as a minor lemma along the way to his true goal in the paper, solving a special case of the decision problem for first-order logic, namely the decidability of what is now called the Bernays–Schönfinkel–Ramsey class of first-order logic, as well as a characterisation of the spectrum of sentences in this fragment of logic. Alonzo Church would go on to show that the general case of the decision problem for first-order logic is unsolvable (see Church's theorem). A great amount of later work in mathematics was fruitfully developed out of the ostensibly minor lemma, which turned out to be an important early result in combinatorics, supporting the idea that within some sufficiently large systems, however disordered, there must be some order. So fruitful, in fact, was Ramsey's theorem that today there is an entire branch of mathematics, known as Ramsey theory, which is dedicated to studying similar results.

Philosophy

His main philosophical works included Universals (1925), Facts and propositions (1927) (which proposed a redundancy theory of truth), Universals of law and of fact (1928), Knowledge (1929), Theories (1929), On Truth (1929), Causal Qualities (1929), and General propositions and causality (1929). Ramsey was perhaps the first to propose a reliablist theory of knowledge.[12] He also produced, what philosopher Alan Hájek has described as an "enormously influential version of the subjective interpretation of probability."[13] His thought in this area was outlined in the paper Truth and Probability (discussed below) which was written in 1926 but first published posthumously in 1931.[14]

Economics

Keynes and Pigou encouraged Ramsey to work on economics as "From a very early age, about sixteen I think, his precocious mind was intensely interested in economic problems" (Keynes, 1933). Ramsey responded to Keynes's urging by writing three papers in economic theory all of which were of fundamental importance, though it was many years before they received their proper recognition by the community of economists.

Ramsey's three papers, described below in detail, were on subjective probability and utility (1926), optimal allocation (1927) and optimal one-sector economic growth (1928). The economist Paul Samuelson described them in 1970 as "three great legacies – legacies that were for the most part mere by-products of his major interest in the foundations of mathematics and knowledge."[15]

A Mathematical Theory of Saving

Described by Partha Dasgupta, in a Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry devoted to it, as "one of the dozen or so most influential papers of the 20th century" in the field of academic economics, "A Mathematical Theory of Saving" was originally published in The Economic Journal in 1928.[16][17] It employed, as Paul Samuelson described it, "a strategically beautiful application of the calculus of variations"[15] to determine the optimal amount an economy should invest rather than consume so as to maximise future utility, or as Ramsey put it, "how much of its income should a nation save?"[17]

Keynes described the article as "one of the most remarkable contributions to mathematical economics ever made, both in respect of the intrinsic importance and difficulty of its subject, the power and elegance of the technical methods employed, and the clear purity of illumination with which the writer's mind is felt by the reader to play about its subject. The article is terribly difficult reading for an economist, but it is not difficult to appreciate how scientific and aesthetic qualities are combined in it together."[18] The Ramsey model is today acknowledged as the starting point for optimal accumulation theory although its importance was not recognised until many years after its first publication.

The main contributions of the model were firstly the initial question Ramsey posed on how much savings should be and secondly the method of analysis, the intertemporal maximisation (optimisation) of collective or individual utility by applying techniques of dynamic optimisation. Tjalling C. Koopmans and David Cass modified the Ramsey model incorporating the dynamic features of population growth at a steady rate and of Harrod-neutral technical progress again at a steady rate, giving birth to a model named the Ramsey–Cass–Koopmans model where the objective now is to maximise household's utility function.

A Contribution to the Theory of Taxation

This paper, first published in 1927 has been described by Joseph E. Stiglitz as "a landmark in the economics of public finance" [19][20] In the same, Ramsey contributed to economic theory the elegant concept of Ramsey pricing. This is applicable in situations where a (regulated) monopolist wants to maximise consumer surplus whilst at the same time ensuring that its costs are adequately covered. This is achieved by setting the price such that the markup over marginal cost is inversely proportional to the price elasticity of demand for that good.. Ramsey poses the question that is to be solved at the beginning of the article: "a given revenue is to be raised by proportionate taxes on some or all uses of income, the taxes on different uses being possibly at different rates; how much should these rates be adjusted in order that the decrement of utility may be a minimum?"[20]. The problem was suggested to him by the economist Arthur Pigou and the paper was Ramsey's answer to the problem.

Truth and Probability

In A Treatise on Probability (1921), Keynes had argued against the subjective approach in epistemic probabilities. For Keynes, subjectivity of probabilities does not matter as much, as for him there is an objective relationship between knowledge and probabilities, as knowledge is disembodied and not personal.

Ramsey disagreed with this approach. In his article "Truth and Probability" (1926), he argued that there is a difference between the notions of probability in physics and in logic.[14] For Ramsey, probability is not related to a disembodied body of knowledge but is related to the knowledge that each individual possesses alone. Thus personal beliefs that are formulated by this individual knowledge govern probabilities, leading to the notions of subjective probability and Bayesian probability. Consequently, subjective probabilities can be inferred by observing actions that reflect individuals' personal beliefs. Ramsey argued that the degree of probability that an individual attaches to a particular outcome can be measured by finding what odds the individual would accept when betting on that outcome.

Ramsey suggested a way of deriving a consistent theory of choice under uncertainty that could isolate beliefs from preferences while still maintaining subjective probabilities.

Despite the fact that Ramsey's work on probabilities was of great importance again no one paid any attention to it until the publication of Theory of Games and Economic Behavior of John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern in 1944 (1947 2nd ed.)

Legacy

Frank P. Ramsey Medal

The Decision Analysis Society[21] annually awards the Frank P. Ramsey Medal[22] to recognise substantial contributions to decision theory and its application to important classes of real decision problems.

Frank Ramsey Professorships

Howard Raiffa was made the first Frank P. Ramsey Professor (of Managerial Economics) at Harvard University. Richard Zeckhauser was made the Frank P. Ramsey Professor of Political Economy at Harvard University in 1971. Raiffa's chair was joint between the Harvard Business and Kennedy Schools. Zeckhauser's chair is in the Kennedy School. Partha Dasgupta was made the Frank Ramsey Professor of Economics in 1994 and Frank Ramsey Professor Emeritus of Economics in 2010 at the University of Cambridge.[23]

See also


Notes

  1. Cheryl Misak, Cambridge Pragmatism: From Peirce and James to Ramsey and Wittgenstein, Oxford University Press, 2016, p. 3.
  2. Ramsey, Frank P.. "Frank P. Ramsey's Papers". Special Collections Department, University of Pittsburgh. http://digital.library.pitt.edu/cgi-bin/f/findaid/findaid-idx?c=ascead&cc=ascead&rgn=main&view=text&didno=US-PPiU-asp198301. Retrieved 19 September 2013. 
  3. Quoted from Ramsey's Diary, 13 January 1924 by Forrester, 2004
  4. "Biography". Archived from the original on 18 July 2016. https://web.archive.org/web/20160718182823/http://www.helenmuspratt-photographer.com/life/biography. Retrieved 29 January 2018. 
  5. "He was certainly sorry that I went on being religious; he was sorry that I decided to become a priest in the Church of England; sorry indeed, but quite tolerant." Quoted in Mellor, "Ramsey", p. 255
  6. Frank P. Ramsey (1925). "Universals". Mind 34 (136): 401–417. doi:10.1093/mind/xxxiv.136.401. http://www.hist-analytic.com/Ramseyonuniversals.htm. 
  7. Frank P. Ramsey (1926). "Foundations of Mathematics". Proc. London Math. Soc. 25: 338–384. doi:10.1112/plms/s2-25.1.338. https://www.gwern.net/docs/math/1926-ramsey.pdf. 
  8. Frank P. Ramsey (1927). "Facts and Propositions". Proc. Aristot. Soc. Suppl. 7: 153–170. https://www.aristoteliansociety.org.uk/pdf/ramsey.pdf. 
  9. Quoted in Mellor, "Ramsey", p. 245,
  10. See Gabriele Taylor (in Galavotti 2006, 1–18) and Duarte (2009a)
  11. A Guide to Churchill College, Cambridge: text by Dr. Mark Goldie, pages 62 and 63 (2009)
  12. Goldman, Alvin; Beddor, Bob (2016), Zalta, Edward N., ed., Reliabilist Epistemology (Winter 2016 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/reliabilism/, retrieved 2019-10-17, "Perhaps the first formulation of a reliability account of knowing appeared in a brief discussion by F.P. Ramsey (1931), who said that a belief is knowledge if it is true, certain and obtained by a reliable process. This attracted no attention at the time and apparently did not influence reliability theories of the 1960s, 70s, or 80s." 
  13. Hájek, Alan (2019), Zalta, Edward N., ed., Interpretations of Probability (Fall 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/probability-interpret/, retrieved 2019-10-19 
  14. 14.0 14.1 F.P. Ramsey (1926) "Truth and Probability", in Ramsey, 1931, The Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays, Ch. VII, p.156-198, edited by R.B. Braithwaite, London: Kegan, Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company 1999 electronic edition
  15. 15.0 15.1 Samuelson, Paul A. (1970). "What Makes for a Beautiful Problem in Science?". Journal of Political Economy 78 (6): 1372–1377. doi:10.1086/259716. 
  16. Dasgupta, Partha (2019), Zalta, Edward N., ed., Ramsey and Intergenerational Welfare Economics (Summer 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/ramsey-economics/, retrieved 2019-10-17 
  17. 17.0 17.1 Ramsey, F. P. (1928). "A Mathematical Theory of Saving". The Economic Journal 38 (152): 543–559. doi:10.2307/2224098. ISSN 0013-0133. http://piketty.pse.ens.fr/files/Ramsey1928.pdf. 
  18. Keynes, J. M. (March 1930). "F. P. Ramsey".The Economic Journal. 40 (157): 153–154. JSTOR 2223657.reprinted in: Keynes J.M. (2010) "F. P. Ramsey", Essays in Biography. Palgrave Macmillan, London, p.335–336
  19. Stiglitz, Joseph E. (2015-03-01). "In Praise of Frank Ramsey's Contribution to the Theory of Taxation" (in en). The Economic Journal 125 (583): 235–268. doi:10.1111/ecoj.12187. ISSN 0013-0133. https://www8.gsb.columbia.edu/faculty/jstiglitz/sites/jstiglitz/files/In%20Praise%20of%20Frank%20Ramsey.pdf. 
  20. 20.0 20.1 Ramsey, F. P. (1927). "A Contribution to the Theory of Taxation". The Economic Journal 37 (145): 47–61. doi:10.2307/2222721. ISSN 0013-0133. 
  21. Decision Analysis Society
  22. Frank P. Ramsey Medal
  23. "CURRICULUM VITAE". Archived from the original on 28 July 2014. https://web.archive.org/web/20140728122132/http://www.econ.cam.ac.uk/people/emeritus/pd10000/CV.pdf. 

References

Further reading

  • Margaret Paul (2012). Frank Ramsey (1903–1930): A Sister's Memoir. Smith-Gordon. ISBN 978-1-85463-248-7. 
  • Karl Sabbagh. Shooting Star: The Brief and Brilliant Life of Frank Ramsey. Amazon Digital Services, Inc., 2013. 75 pages.

External links