Fréchet inequalities

From HandWiki

In probabilistic logic, the Fréchet inequalities, also known as the Boole–Fréchet inequalities, are rules implicit in the work of George Boole[1][2] and explicitly derived by Maurice Fréchet[3][4] that govern the combination of probabilities about logical propositions or events logically linked together in conjunctions (AND operations) or disjunctions (OR operations) as in Boolean expressions or fault or event trees common in risk assessments, engineering design and artificial intelligence. These inequalities can be considered rules about how to bound calculations involving probabilities without assuming independence or, indeed, without making any dependence assumptions whatsoever. The Fréchet inequalities are closely related to the Boole–Bonferroni–Fréchet inequalities, and to Fréchet bounds. If Ai are logical propositions or events, the Fréchet inequalities are

  • Probability of a logical conjunction ([math]\displaystyle{ \land }[/math]) [math]\displaystyle{ \max\left(0, \, \sum_{k = 1}^n \mathbb{P}(A_k) - (n - 1)\right) \leq \mathbb{P}\left(\bigwedge_{k = 1}^n A_k\right) \leq \min_k\{\mathbb{P}(A_k)\}, }[/math]
  • Probability of a logical disjunction ([math]\displaystyle{ \lor }[/math]) [math]\displaystyle{ \max_k\{\mathbb{P}(A_k)\} \leq \mathbb{P}\left(\bigvee_{k = 1}^n A_k\right) \leq \min\left(1, \, \sum_{k = 1}^n \mathbb{P}(A_k)\right), }[/math]

where P( ) denotes the probability of an event or proposition. In the case where there are only two events, say A and B, the inequalities reduce to

  • Probability of a logical conjunction ([math]\displaystyle{ \land }[/math]) [math]\displaystyle{ \max(0, \, \mathbb{P}(A) + \mathbb{P}(B) - 1) \leq \mathbb{P}(A \land B) \leq \min(\mathbb{P}(A), \, \mathbb{P}(B)), }[/math]
  • Probability of a logical disjunction ([math]\displaystyle{ \lor }[/math]) [math]\displaystyle{ \max(\mathbb{P}(A), \, \mathbb{P}(B)) \leq \mathbb{P}(A \lor B) \leq \min(1, \, \mathbb{P}(A) + \mathbb{P}(B)). }[/math]

The inequalities bound the probabilities of the two kinds of joint events given the probabilities of the individual events. For example, if A is "has lung cancer", and B is "has mesothelioma", then A & B is "has both lung cancer and mesothelioma", and A ∨ B is "has lung cancer or mesothelioma or both diseases", and the inequalities relate the risks of these events.

Note that logical conjunctions are denoted in various ways in different fields, including AND, &, ∧ and graphical AND-gates. Logical disjunctions are likewise denoted in various ways, including OR, |, ∨, and graphical OR-gates. If events are taken to be sets rather than logical propositions, the set-theoretic versions of the Fréchet inequalities are

  • Probability of an intersection of events [math]\displaystyle{ \max(0, \, \mathbb{P}(A) + \mathbb{P}(B) - 1) \leq \mathbb{P}(A \cap B) \leq \min(\mathbb{P}(A), \, \mathbb{P}(B)), }[/math]
  • Probability of a union of events [math]\displaystyle{ \max(\mathbb{P}(A), \, \mathbb{P}(B)) \leq \mathbb{P}(A \cup B) \leq \min(1, \, \mathbb{P}(A) + \mathbb{P}(B)). }[/math]

Numerical examples

If the probability of an event A is P(A) = a = 0.7, and the probability of the event B is P(B) = b = 0.8, then the probability of the conjunction, i.e., the joint event A & B, is surely in the interval [math]\displaystyle{ \begin{align} \mathbb{P}(A \land B) &\in [\max(0, \, a + b - 1), \, \min(a, \, b)] \\ &= [\max(0, \, 0.7 + 0.8 - 1), \, \min(0.7, \, 0.8)] \\ &= [0.5, \, 0.7] \end{align}. }[/math] Likewise, the probability of the disjunction A ∨ B is surely in the interval [math]\displaystyle{ \begin{align} \mathbb{P}(A \lor B) &\in [\max(a, \, b), \, \min(1, \, a + b)] \\ &= [\max(0.7, \, 0.8), \, \min(1, \, 0.7 + 0.8)] \\ &= [0.8, \, 1] \end{align}. }[/math]

These intervals are contrasted with the results obtained from the rules of probability assuming independence, where the probability of the conjunction is P(A & B) = a × b = 0.7 × 0.8 = 0.56, and the probability of the disjunction is P(A ∨ B) = a + ba × b = 0.94.

When the marginal probabilities are very small (or large), the Fréchet intervals are strongly asymmetric about the analogous results under independence. For example, suppose P(A) = 0.000002 = 2×10−6 and P(B) = 0.000003 = 3×10−6. Then the Fréchet inequalities say P(A & B) is in the interval [0, 2×10−6], and P(A ∨ B) is in the interval [3×10−6, 5×10−6]. If A and B are independent, however, the probability of A & B is 6×10−12 which is, comparatively, very close to the lower limit (zero) of the Fréchet interval. Similarly, the probability of A ∨ B is 4.999994×10−6, which is very close to the upper limit of the Fréchet interval. This is what justifies the rare-event approximation[5] often used in reliability theory.

Proofs

The proofs are elementary. Recall that P(AB) = P(A) + P(B) − P(A & B), which implies P(A) + P(B) − P(AB) = P(A & B). Because all probabilities are no bigger than 1, we know P(AB) ≤ 1, which implies that P(A) + P(B) − 1 ≤ P(A & B). Because all probabilities are also positive we can similarly say 0 ≤ P(A & B), so max(0, P(A) + P(B) − 1) ≤ P(A & B). This gives the lower bound on the conjunction.

To get the upper bound, recall that P(A & B) = P(A|B) P(B) = P(B|A) P(A). Because P(A|B) ≤ 1 and P(B|A) ≤ 1, we know P(A & B) ≤ P(A) and P(A & B) ≤ P(B). Therefore, P(A & B) ≤ min(P(A), P(B)), which is the upper bound.

The best-possible nature of these bounds follows from observing that they are realized by some dependency between the events A and B. Comparable bounds on the disjunction are similarly derived.

Extensions

When the input probabilities are themselves interval ranges, the Fréchet formulas still work as a probability bounds analysis. Hailperin[2] considered the problem of evaluating probabilistic Boolean expressions involving many events in complex conjunctions and disjunctions. Some[6][7] have suggested using the inequalities in various applications of artificial intelligence and have extended the rules to account for various assumptions about the dependence among the events. The inequalities can also be generalized to other logical operations, including even modus ponens.[6][8] When the input probabilities are characterized by probability distributions, analogous operations that generalize logical and arithmetic convolutions without assumptions about the dependence between the inputs can be defined based on the related notion of Fréchet bounds.[7][9][10]

Quantum Fréchet bounds

Similar bounds hold also in quantum mechanics in the case of separable quantum systems and that entangled states violate these bounds.[11] Consider a composite quantum system. In particular, we focus on a composite quantum system AB made by two finite subsystems denoted as A and B. Assume that we know the density matrix of the subsystem A, i.e., [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^A }[/math] that is a trace-one positive definite matrix in [math]\displaystyle{ \Complex_{h}^{n\times n} }[/math] (the space of Hermitian matrices of dimension [math]\displaystyle{ n \times n }[/math]), and the density matrix of subsystem B denoted as [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^B. }[/math] We can think of [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^A }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^B }[/math] as the marginals of the subsystems A and B. From the knowledge of these marginals, we want to infer something about the joint [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^{AB} }[/math] in [math]\displaystyle{ \Complex_{h}^{nm\times nm}. }[/math] We restrict our attention to joint [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^{AB} }[/math] that are separable. A density matrix on a composite system is separable if there exist [math]\displaystyle{ p_k\geq 0, \{\rho_1^k \} }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ \{ \rho_2^k \} }[/math] which are mixed states of the respective subsystems such that [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^{AB}=\sum_k p_k \rho_1^k \otimes \rho_2^k }[/math] where [math]\displaystyle{ \sum_k p_k = 1. }[/math]

Otherwise [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^{AB} }[/math] is called an entangled state.

For separable density matrices [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^{AB} }[/math] in [math]\displaystyle{ \Complex_{h}^{nm\times nm} }[/math] the following Fréchet like bounds hold:

[math]\displaystyle{ \begin{cases} \rho^{AB} \leq \rho^{A} \otimes I_m \\ \rho^{AB} \leq I_n \otimes \rho^{B} \\[6pt] \rho^{AB} \geq \rho^A \otimes I_m + I_n \otimes \rho^B-I_{nm} \\ \rho^{AB} \gneq 0 \end{cases} }[/math]

The inequalities are matrix inequalities, [math]\displaystyle{ \otimes }[/math] denotes the tensor product and [math]\displaystyle{ I_x }[/math] the identity matrix of dimension [math]\displaystyle{ x }[/math]. It is evident that structurally the above inequalities are analogues of the classical Fréchet bounds for the logical conjunction. It is also worth to notice that when the matrices [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^A,\rho^B }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^{AB} }[/math] are restricted to be diagonal, we obtain the classical Fréchet bounds.

The upper bound is known in Quantum Mechanics as reduction criterion for density matrices; it was first proven by[12] and independently formulated by.[13] The lower bound has been obtained in[11](Theorem A.16) that provides a Bayesian interpretation of these bounds.

Numerical examples

We have observed when the matrices [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^A,\rho^B }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^{AB} }[/math] are all diagonal, we obtain the classical Fréchet bounds. To show that, consider again the previous numerical example:

[math]\displaystyle{ \begin{align} \rho^A & = \text{diag}(p_{a},p_{\bar{a}})=\text{diag}(0.7,0.3) \\ \rho^B & = \text{diag}(p_{b},p_{\bar{b}})=\text{diag}(0.8,0.2) \end{align} }[/math]

then we have: [math]\displaystyle{ \begin{align} \rho^{AB}&= \text{diag}(p_{ab},p_{a\bar{b}},p_{\bar{a}b},p_{\bar{a}\bar{b}}) \leqslant \rho^{A} \otimes I_2 =\text{diag}(0.7,0.7,0.3,0.3) \\ \rho^{AB}&= \text{diag}(p_{ab},p_{a\bar{b}},p_{\bar{a}b},p_{\bar{a}\bar{b}}) \leqslant I_2 \otimes \rho^{B} =\text{diag}(0.8,0.2,0.8,0.2) \\ \rho^{AB}&= \text{diag}(p_{ab},p_{a\bar{b}},p_{\bar{a}b},p_{\bar{a}\bar{b}}) \geqslant \rho^{A} \otimes I_2 + I_2 \otimes \rho^{B} - I_4 = \text{diag}(0.5, -0.1, 0.1, -0.5) \\ \rho^{AB}&=\text{diag}(p_{ab},p_{a\bar{b}},p_{\bar{a}b},p_{\bar{a}\bar{b}}) \geqslant 0 \end{align} }[/math]

which means:

[math]\displaystyle{ \begin{align} 0.5 &\leqslant p_{ab} \leqslant 0.7 \\ 0 &\leqslant p_{a\bar{b}} \leqslant 0.2 \\ 0.1 &\leqslant p_{\bar{a}b} \leqslant 0.3 \\ 0 &\leqslant p_{\bar{a}\bar{b}} \leqslant 0.2 \end{align} }[/math]

It is worth to point out that entangled states violate the above Fréchet bounds. Consider for instance the entangled density matrix (which is not separable):

[math]\displaystyle{ \rho^{AB} = \frac{1}{2} \begin{bmatrix} 1 & 0 & 0 & 1\\ 0 & 0 & 0 & 0\\ 0 & 0 & 0 & 0\\ 1 & 0 & 0 & 1\\ \end{bmatrix}, }[/math]

which has marginal [math]\displaystyle{ \rho^A=\rho^B=\text{diag}\left(\tfrac{1}{2}, \tfrac{1}{2} \right). }[/math]

Entangled states are not separable and it can easily be verified that [math]\displaystyle{ \begin{cases} \rho^A \otimes I_m-\rho^{AB} \ngeqslant0 \\ I_n \otimes \rho^B -\rho^{AB} \ngeqslant0 \end{cases} }[/math]

since the resulting matrices have one negative eigenvalue.

Another example of violation of probabilistic bounds is provided by the famous Bell's inequality: entangled states exhibit a form of stochastic dependence stronger than the strongest classical dependence: and in fact they violate Fréchet like bounds.

See also

References

  1. Boole, G. (1854). An Investigation of the Laws of Thought, On Which Are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probability. Walton and Maberly, London. See Boole's "major" and "minor" limits of a conjunction on page 299.
  2. 2.0 2.1 Hailperin, T. (1986). Boole's Logic and Probability. North-Holland, Amsterdam.
  3. Fréchet, M. (1935). Généralisations du théorème des probabilités totales. Fundamenta Mathematicae 25: 379–387.
  4. Fréchet, M. (1951). Sur les tableaux de corrélation dont les marges sont données. Annales de l'Université de Lyon. Section A: Sciences mathématiques et astronomie 9: 53–77.
  5. Collet, J. (1996). Some remarks on rare-event approximation. IEEE Transactions on Reliability 45: 106–108.
  6. 6.0 6.1 Wise, B.P., and M. Henrion (1986). A framework for comparing uncertain inference systems to probability. Uncertainty in Artificial Intelligence, edited by L.N. Kanal and J.F. Lemmer, Elsevier Science Publishers, B.V. North-Holland, Amsterdam.
  7. 7.0 7.1 Williamson, R.C. (1989). Probabilistic Arithmetic. Dissertation, University of Queensland.
  8. Wagner, C.G. (2004). Modus tollens probabilized. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55: 747–753.
  9. Weisstein, Eric W. Fréchet bounds. MathWorld--A Wolfram Web Resource.
  10. Rüschendorf, L. (1991). Fréchet-bounds and their applications. Pages 151–187 in Advances in Probability Distributions with Given Marginals, Mathematics and Its Applications 67, edited by G. Dall'Aglio, S. Kotz and G. Salinetti, Kluwer, Dordrecht.
  11. 11.0 11.1 Benavoli, A.; Facchini, A.; Zaffalon, M. (10 October 2016). "Quantum mechanics: The Bayesian theory generalized to the space of Hermitian matrices". Physical Review A 94 (4): 042106. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.94.042106. Bibcode2016PhRvA..94d2106B. http://journals.aps.org/pra/abstract/10.1103/PhysRevA.94.042106. 
  12. M. Horodecki and P. Horodecki (1999). "Reduction criterion of separability and limits for a class of distillation protocols". Phys. Rev. A 59 (6): 4206–4216. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.59.4206. Bibcode1999PhRvA..59.4206H. 
  13. N. Cerf (1999). "Reduction criterion for separability". Phys. Rev. A 60 (2): 898–909. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.60.898. Bibcode1999PhRvA..60..898C.