Paradox of voting

From HandWiki
Revision as of 07:03, 18 May 2023 by Unex (talk | contribs) (change)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Short description: Aspect of politics
A crowd of voters queuing at a polling station in Caracas

The paradox of voting, also called Downs' paradox, is that for a rational, self-interested voter, the costs of voting will normally exceed the expected benefits. Because the chance of exercising the pivotal vote is minuscule compared to any realistic estimate of the private individual benefits of the different possible outcomes, the expected benefits of voting are less than the costs.

Responses to the paradox have included the view that voters vote to express their preference for a candidate rather than affect the outcome of the election, that voters exercise some degree of altruism, or that the paradox ignores the collateral benefits associated with voting besides the resulting electoral outcome.

History of scholarship

The issue was noted by Nicolas de Condorcet in 1793 when he stated, "In single-stage elections, where there are a great many voters, each voter's influence is very small. It is therefore possible that the citizens will not be sufficiently interested [to vote]" and "... we know that this interest [which voters have in an election] must decrease with each individual's [i.e. voter's] influence on the election and as the number of voters increases."[1]

In 1821, Hegel made a similar observation in his Elements of the Philosophy of Right: "As for popular suffrage, it may be further remarked that especially in large states it leads inevitably to electoral indifference, since the casting of a single vote is of no significance where there is a multitude of electors."[2][3]

The mathematician Charles L. Dodgson, better known as Lewis Carroll, published the paper "A Method of Taking Votes on More than Two Issues" in 1876.[4]

This problem in modern public choice theory was analysed by Anthony Downs in 1957.[5]

Responses

Alternative responses modify the postulate of egoistic rationality in various ways. For example, Geoffrey Brennan and Loren Lomasky suggest that voters derive "expressive" benefits from supporting particular candidates – analogous to cheering on a sports team – rather than voting in hopes of achieving the political outcomes they prefer. This implies that the rational behavior of voters is restricted to the instrumental as opposed to the intrinsic value they derive from their vote.[6][7]

Another suggestion, known as the altruism theory of voting, is that voters are rational but not fully egoistic. In this view voters have some degree of altruism, and perceive a benefit if others are benefited. Since an election affects many others, it could still be rational to cast a vote with only a small chance of affecting the outcome.[8]


See also

References

  1. Mclean, I. & Hewitt, F. (1994), Condorcet, Edward Elgar Publishing, Brookfield, VT, pp. 245–246.[ISBN missing]
  2. Terence Ball (1987), "Is There Progress in Political Science?", Idioms of Inquiry (SUNY): p. 30, ISBN 978-0887064586, https://archive.org/details/idiomsofinquiryc0000unse/page/30 
  3. Buchanan, James (1974), "Hegel on the calculus of voting", Public Choice 17 (1): 99–101, doi:10.1007/BF01719001 
  4. Black, D. (1987). The Theory of Committees and Elections. Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 46–51. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-4225-7_7. ISBN 978-9400942257. 
  5. Downs, A. (1957), An Economic Theory of Democracy, Harper and Row, N.Y., 1957.[page needed][ISBN missing]
  6. Brennan, Geoffrey; Lomasky, Loren (1997). Democracy and Decision: The Pure Theory of Electoral Preference. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521350433. [page needed]
  7. Brennan, Geoffrey; Hamlin, Alan (1998). "Expressive Voting and Electoral Equilibrium". Public Choice 95: 149–175. doi:10.1023/A:1004936203144. https://link.springer.com/article/10.1023/A:1004936203144. Retrieved 2 June 2021. 
  8. Edlin, Aaron, Andrew Gelman, and Noah Kaplan. "Voting as a Rational Choice: Why and How People Vote To Improve the Well-Being of Others." Rationality and Society. 19.3 (2008): 293–314. Web. 22 Oct. 2012.