MV-algebra
This article needs editing for compliance with Wikipedia's Manual of Style. In particular, it has problems with MOS:BBB. (July 2023) (Learn how and when to remove this template message) |
In abstract algebra, a branch of pure mathematics, an MV-algebra is an algebraic structure with a binary operation [math]\displaystyle{ \oplus }[/math], a unary operation [math]\displaystyle{ \neg }[/math], and the constant [math]\displaystyle{ 0 }[/math], satisfying certain axioms. MV-algebras are the algebraic semantics of Łukasiewicz logic; the letters MV refer to the many-valued logic of Łukasiewicz. MV-algebras coincide with the class of bounded commutative BCK algebras.
Definitions
An MV-algebra is an algebraic structure [math]\displaystyle{ \langle A, \oplus, \lnot, 0\rangle, }[/math] consisting of
- a non-empty set [math]\displaystyle{ A, }[/math]
- a binary operation [math]\displaystyle{ \oplus }[/math] on [math]\displaystyle{ A, }[/math]
- a unary operation [math]\displaystyle{ \lnot }[/math] on [math]\displaystyle{ A, }[/math] and
- a constant [math]\displaystyle{ 0 }[/math] denoting a fixed element of [math]\displaystyle{ A, }[/math]
which satisfies the following identities:
- [math]\displaystyle{ (x \oplus y) \oplus z = x \oplus (y \oplus z), }[/math]
- [math]\displaystyle{ x \oplus 0 = x, }[/math]
- [math]\displaystyle{ x \oplus y = y \oplus x, }[/math]
- [math]\displaystyle{ \lnot \lnot x = x, }[/math]
- [math]\displaystyle{ x \oplus \lnot 0 = \lnot 0, }[/math] and
- [math]\displaystyle{ \lnot ( \lnot x \oplus y)\oplus y = \lnot ( \lnot y \oplus x) \oplus x. }[/math]
By virtue of the first three axioms, [math]\displaystyle{ \langle A, \oplus, 0 \rangle }[/math] is a commutative monoid. Being defined by identities, MV-algebras form a variety of algebras. The variety of MV-algebras is a subvariety of the variety of BL-algebras and contains all Boolean algebras.
An MV-algebra can equivalently be defined (Hájek 1998) as a prelinear commutative bounded integral residuated lattice [math]\displaystyle{ \langle L, \wedge, \vee, \otimes, \rightarrow, 0, 1 \rangle }[/math] satisfying the additional identity [math]\displaystyle{ x \vee y = (x \rightarrow y) \rightarrow y. }[/math]
Examples of MV-algebras
A simple numerical example is [math]\displaystyle{ A=[0,1], }[/math] with operations [math]\displaystyle{ x \oplus y = \min(x + y, 1) }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ \lnot x = 1 - x. }[/math] In mathematical fuzzy logic, this MV-algebra is called the standard MV-algebra, as it forms the standard real-valued semantics of Łukasiewicz logic.
The trivial MV-algebra has the only element 0 and the operations defined in the only possible way, [math]\displaystyle{ 0\oplus0=0 }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ \lnot0=0. }[/math]
The two-element MV-algebra is actually the two-element Boolean algebra [math]\displaystyle{ \{0,1\}, }[/math] with [math]\displaystyle{ \oplus }[/math] coinciding with Boolean disjunction and [math]\displaystyle{ \lnot }[/math] with Boolean negation. In fact adding the axiom [math]\displaystyle{ x \oplus x = x }[/math] to the axioms defining an MV-algebra results in an axiomatization of Boolean algebras.
If instead the axiom added is [math]\displaystyle{ x \oplus x \oplus x = x \oplus x }[/math], then the axioms define the MV3 algebra corresponding to the three-valued Łukasiewicz logic Ł3[citation needed]. Other finite linearly ordered MV-algebras are obtained by restricting the universe and operations of the standard MV-algebra to the set of [math]\displaystyle{ n }[/math] equidistant real numbers between 0 and 1 (both included), that is, the set [math]\displaystyle{ \{0,1/(n-1),2/(n-1),\dots,1\}, }[/math] which is closed under the operations [math]\displaystyle{ \oplus }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ \lnot }[/math] of the standard MV-algebra; these algebras are usually denoted MVn.
Another important example is Chang's MV-algebra, consisting just of infinitesimals (with the order type ω) and their co-infinitesimals.
Chang also constructed an MV-algebra from an arbitrary totally ordered abelian group G by fixing a positive element u and defining the segment [0, u] as { x ∈ G | 0 ≤ x ≤ u }, which becomes an MV-algebra with x ⊕ y = min(u, x + y) and ¬x = u − x. Furthermore, Chang showed that every linearly ordered MV-algebra is isomorphic to an MV-algebra constructed from a group in this way.
Daniele Mundici extended the above construction to abelian lattice-ordered groups. If G is such a group with strong (order) unit u, then the "unit interval" { x ∈ G | 0 ≤ x ≤ u } can be equipped with ¬x = u − x, x ⊕ y = u ∧G (x + y), and x ⊗ y = 0 ∨G (x + y − u). This construction establishes a categorical equivalence between lattice-ordered abelian groups with strong unit and MV-algebras.
An effect algebra that is lattice-ordered and has the Riesz decomposition property is an MV-algebra. Conversely, any MV-algebra is a lattice-ordered effect algebra with the Riesz decomposition property.[1]
Relation to Łukasiewicz logic
C. C. Chang devised MV-algebras to study many-valued logics, introduced by Jan Łukasiewicz in 1920. In particular, MV-algebras form the algebraic semantics of Łukasiewicz logic, as described below.
Given an MV-algebra A, an A-valuation is a homomorphism from the algebra of propositional formulas (in the language consisting of [math]\displaystyle{ \oplus,\lnot, }[/math] and 0) into A. Formulas mapped to 1 (that is, to [math]\displaystyle{ \lnot }[/math]0) for all A-valuations are called A-tautologies. If the standard MV-algebra over [0,1] is employed, the set of all [0,1]-tautologies determines so-called infinite-valued Łukasiewicz logic.
Chang's (1958, 1959) completeness theorem states that any MV-algebra equation holding in the standard MV-algebra over the interval [0,1] will hold in every MV-algebra. Algebraically, this means that the standard MV-algebra generates the variety of all MV-algebras. Equivalently, Chang's completeness theorem says that MV-algebras characterize infinite-valued Łukasiewicz logic, defined as the set of [0,1]-tautologies.
The way the [0,1] MV-algebra characterizes all possible MV-algebras parallels the well-known fact that identities holding in the two-element Boolean algebra hold in all possible Boolean algebras. Moreover, MV-algebras characterize infinite-valued Łukasiewicz logic in a manner analogous to the way that Boolean algebras characterize classical bivalent logic (see Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra).
In 1984, Font, Rodriguez and Torrens introduced the Wajsberg algebra as an alternative model for the infinite-valued Łukasiewicz logic. Wajsberg algebras and MV-algebras are term-equivalent.[2]
MVn-algebras
In the 1940s Grigore Moisil introduced his Łukasiewicz–Moisil algebras (LMn-algebras) in the hope of giving algebraic semantics for the (finitely) n-valued Łukasiewicz logic. However, in 1956 Alan Rose discovered that for n ≥ 5, the Łukasiewicz–Moisil algebra does not model the Łukasiewicz n-valued logic. Although C. C. Chang published his MV-algebra in 1958, it is a faithful model only for the ℵ0-valued (infinitely-many-valued) Łukasiewicz–Tarski logic. For the axiomatically more complicated (finitely) n-valued Łukasiewicz logics, suitable algebras were published in 1977 by Revaz Grigolia and called MVn-algebras.[3] MVn-algebras are a subclass of LMn-algebras; the inclusion is strict for n ≥ 5.[4]
The MVn-algebras are MV-algebras that satisfy some additional axioms, just like the n-valued Łukasiewicz logics have additional axioms added to the ℵ0-valued logic.
In 1982 Roberto Cignoli published some additional constraints that added to LMn-algebras yield proper models for n-valued Łukasiewicz logic; Cignoli called his discovery proper n-valued Łukasiewicz algebras.[5] The LMn-algebras that are also MVn-algebras are precisely Cignoli’s proper n-valued Łukasiewicz algebras.[6]
Relation to functional analysis
MV-algebras were related by Daniele Mundici to approximately finite-dimensional C*-algebras by establishing a bijective correspondence between all isomorphism classes of approximately finite-dimensional C*-algebras with lattice-ordered dimension group and all isomorphism classes of countable MV algebras. Some instances of this correspondence include:
Countable MV algebra | approximately finite-dimensional C*-algebra |
---|---|
{0, 1} | ℂ |
{0, 1/n, ..., 1 } | Mn(ℂ), i.e. n×n complex matrices |
finite | finite-dimensional |
boolean | commutative |
In software
There are multiple frameworks implementing fuzzy logic (type II), and most of them implement what has been called a multi-adjoint logic. This is no more than the implementation of an MV-algebra.
References
- ↑ Foulis, D. J. (2000-10-01). "MV and Heyting Effect Algebras" (in en). Foundations of Physics 30 (10): 1687–1706. doi:10.1023/A:1026454318245. ISSN 1572-9516.
- ↑ "citing J. M. Font, A. J. Rodriguez, A. Torrens, "Wajsberg Algebras", Stochastica, VIII, 1, 5-31, 1984". http://journal.univagora.ro/download/pdf/28.pdf.
- ↑ Lavinia Corina Ciungu (2013). Non-commutative Multiple-Valued Logic Algebras. Springer. pp. vii–viii. ISBN 978-3-319-01589-7.
- ↑ Iorgulescu, A.: Connections between MVn-algebras and n-valued Łukasiewicz–Moisil algebras—I. Discrete Math. 181, 155–177 (1998) doi:10.1016/S0012-365X(97)00052-6
- ↑ R. Cignoli, Proper n-Valued Łukasiewicz Algebras as S-Algebras of Łukasiewicz n-Valued Propositional Calculi, Studia Logica, 41, 1982, 3-16, doi:10.1007/BF00373490
- ↑ "Archived copy". http://journal.univagora.ro/download/pdf/28.pdf.
- Chang, C. C. (1958) "Algebraic analysis of many-valued logics," Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 88: 476–490.
- ------ (1959) "A new proof of the completeness of the Lukasiewicz axioms," Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 88: 74–80.
- Cignoli, R. L. O., D'Ottaviano, I. M. L., Mundici, D. (2000) Algebraic Foundations of Many-valued Reasoning. Kluwer.
- Di Nola A., Lettieri A. (1993) "Equational characterization of all varieties of MV-algebras," Journal of Algebra 221: 463–474 doi: 10.1006/jabr.1999.7900.
- Hájek, Petr (1998) Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic. Kluwer.
- Mundici, D.: Interpretation of AF C*-algebras in Łukasiewicz sentential calculus. J. Funct. Anal. 65, 15–63 (1986) doi:10.1016/0022-1236(86)90015-7
Further reading
- Daniele Mundici, MV-ALGEBRAS. A short tutorial
- D. Mundici (2011). Advanced Łukasiewicz calculus and MV-algebras. Springer. ISBN 978-94-007-0839-6.
- Mundici, D. The C*-Algebras of Three-Valued Logic. Logic Colloquium ’88, Proceedings of the Colloquium held in Padova 61–77 (1989). doi:10.1016/s0049-237x(08)70262-3
- Cabrer, L. M. & Mundici, D. A Stone-Weierstrass theorem for MV-algebras and unital ℓ-groups. Journal of Logic and Computation (2014). doi:10.1093/logcom/exu023
- Olivia Caramello, Anna Carla Russo (2014) The Morita-equivalence between MV-algebras and abelian ℓ-groups with strong unit
External links
Original source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/MV-algebra.
Read more |