Philosophy:Early modern philosophy

From HandWiki
Short description: Period in the history of philosophy

Early modern philosophy (also classical modern philosophy)[1][2] The early modern era of philosophy was a progressive movement of Western thought, exploring through theories and discourse such topics as mind and matter, is a period in the history of philosophy that overlaps with the beginning of the period known as modern philosophy. It succeeded in the medieval era of philosophy. Early modern philosophy is usually thought to have occurred between the 16th and 18th centuries, though some philosophers and historians may put this period slightly earlier. During this time, influential philosophers included Descartes, Locke, Hume, and Kant, all of whom contributed to the current understanding of philosophy.

Overview

The early modern period in history is around c. 1500–1789, but the label "early modern philosophy" is typically used to refer to a narrower period of time.[3]

In the narrowest sense, the term is used to refer principally to the philosophy of the 17th century and 18th century, typically beginning with René Descartes. 17th-century philosophers typically included in such analyses are Thomas Hobbes, Blaise Pascal, Baruch Spinoza, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, and Isaac Newton. The 18th century, often known as the Age of Enlightenment, included such early modern figures as John Locke, George Berkeley, and David Hume.[2]

The term is sometimes used more broadly, including earlier thinkers from the 16th century such as Niccolò Machiavelli, Martin Luther, John Calvin, Michel de Montaigne, and Francis Bacon.[4] Some definitions also broaden the range of thinkers included under the "early modern" moniker, such as Voltaire, Giambattista Vico, Thomas Paine. By the broadest definition, the early modern period is said to have ended in 1804 with the death of Immanuel Kant. Considered in this way, the period extends from the last Renaissance philosophers to the final days of the Age of Enlightenment.

Early modern European philosophy

Most scholars consider the period to begin with René DescartesMeditationes de Prima Philosophiae (Meditations on First Philosophy) in Paris in 1641 and conclude with the work of the German philosopher Immanuel Kant (Critique of Pure Reason) in the 1780s.[5]

Dispute between Queen Christina and René Descartes

At the time, various thinkers faced difficult philosophical challenges: reconciling the tenets of classical Aristotelian thought and Christian theology with the new technological advances that followed in the wake of Copernicus, Galileo, and Newton.[6] A modern mechanical image of the cosmos in which mathematically definable universal laws directed the motion of lifeless objects without the interference of something non-physical, specifically challenged established ways of thought about the mind, body and God. In response, philosophers, many of whom were involved in experimental advances, invented and perfected various perspectives on humans’ relationship to the cosmos.[7]

Three critical historical events that shaped Western thought profoundly were the Age of Discovery, the progress of modern science, and the Protestant Reformation and its resulting civil wars.[8] The relationship between philosophy and scientific research was complicated, as many early modern scientists considered themselves philosophers, conflating the two disciplines.[9] These two fields would eventually separate. Contemporary philosophy's epistemological and methodological concerns about scientific certainty remained regardless of such a separation.[10]

The early modern intellectual era also contributed to the development of Western philosophy. New philosophical theories, such as the metaphysical, civic existence, epistemology, and rationalist thinking, were established.[11] There was a strong emphasis on the advancement and expansion of rationalism, which placed a premium on rationality, reasoning, and discovery to pursue reality.[12]

Enlightenment Period

The Enlightenment, also referred to as the Age of Enlightenment, was a philosophical movement that dominated the realm of ideas in 18th-century Europe. It was founded on the principle that reason is the fundamental source of power and legitimacy, and it promoted principles such as liberty, progress, tolerance, fraternity, constitutional governance, and church-state separation. The Enlightenment was defined by a focus on science and reductionism, as well as a growing suspicion of religious rigidity. The Enlightenment's ideals challenged the monarchy and the church, laying the groundwork for the political upheavals of the 18th and 19th centuries. According to French historians, the Age of Enlightenment began in 1715, the year Louis XIV died, and ended in 1789, the year of the French Revolution . According to some contemporary historians, the era begins in the 1620s, with the birth of the scientific revolution. However, during the first decades of the 18th century and the first decades of the 19th century, several national variations of the movement developed.

Enlightenment discussions between various thinkers

The Englishmen Francis Bacon and Thomas Hobbes, the Frenchman René Descartes, and the prominent natural philosophers of the Scientific Revolution, including Galileo Galilei, Johannes Kepler, and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, were significant 17th-century antecedents of the Enlightenment. Its origins are often ascribed to 1680s England, when Isaac Newton published his "Principia Mathematica" (1686) and John Locke wrote his "Essay Concerning Human Understanding" (1689)—two works that laid the groundwork for the Enlightenment's great advancements in science, mathematics, and philosophy.[13]

The Age Of Enlightenment was swiftly sweeping across Europe. In the late seventeenth century, scientists such as Isaac Newton and authors such as John Locke challenged the established order. Newton's principles of gravity and motion defined the universe in terms of natural principles that were independent of any spiritual source. Locke advocated the freedom of a people to replace a government that did not defend inherent rights to life, liberty, and property in the aftermath of England's political instability. People began to mistrust the possibility of a God capable of predestining human beings to everlasting damnation and empowering a despotic ruler to rule. These ideals would permanently alter Europe.

Major Enlightenment concepts

Europe had a burst of philosophical and scientific activity in the mid-18th century, challenging established theories and dogmas.[14] Voltaire and Jean-Jacques Rousseau headed the philosophic movement, arguing for a society founded on reason rather than religion and Catholic theology, for a new civic order based on natural law, and for science founded on experimentation and observation.[15] Montesquieu, a political philosopher, proposed the notion of a government's division of powers, which was enthusiastically accepted by the framers of the United States Constitution.[16]

Two separate schools of Enlightenment philosophy existed. Inspired by Spinoza's theory, the radical enlightenment argued for democracy, individual liberty, freedom of speech, and the abolition of religious authority.[17] A second, more moderate kind, championed by René Descartes, John Locke, Christian Wolff, and Isaac Newton, aimed to strike a balance between reform and old power and religious institutions.[18]

Science eventually began to dominate Enlightenment speech and thinking.[19] Numerous Enlightenment authors and intellectuals came from scientific backgrounds and equated scientific progress with the downfall of religion and conventional authority in favour of the growth of free speech and ideas.[20] In general, Enlightenment science placed a high premium on empiricism and logical reasoning, and was inextricably linked to the Enlightenment ideal of progression and development.[21] However, as was the case with the majority of Enlightenment ideals, the advantages of science were not widely recognized.[22]

The Enlightenment has traditionally been credited with laying the groundwork for current Western political and intellectual culture.[23] It ushered in a period of political modernization in the West, focused on democratic principles and institutions and resulting in the establishment of modern, liberal democracies. The fundamentals of European liberal thought include the individual right, natural equality of all men, separation of powers, the artificial nature of political order (which resulted in the later distinction between civil society and the state), the view that all legitimate political power must be "representative" and based on popular consent, and liberal interpretationism.[24]

Enlightenment-era criticism on religion was a reaction to Europe's previous century of religious turmoil.[25] Enlightenment intellectuals intended to limit organized religion's political dominance, so averting another period of intolerable religious violence.[26] Numerous unique concepts emerged, including deism (belief in God the Creator without reference to the Bible or other authoritative source) and atheism.[27] The latter was hotly debated but garnered few supporters. Many, like Voltaire, believed that without believing in a God who punishes wrong, society's moral order would be jeopardised.[28]

Characteristics

The early modern period arose from dramatic shifts in many fields of human endeavour. Among the most significant characteristics are the formalisation of science, the acceleration of scientific advancement, and the creation of secularised civic politics, law courts, and the nation-state.[29] There was some skepticism against traditional interpretive concepts associated with the modern era, such as the distinction between empiricists and rationalists, which represented a philosophical and historical shift away from ethics, political philosophy, and metaphysical epistemology.[30]

Individualism also emerged as a reaction to belief and authority, challenging the element of Christianity and Christianised philosophy united with whoever the desired political leader happened to be at the time.[31] The steady rise of the bourgeoisie would challenge the power of the Church and begin the journey towards the eventual separation of church and state. The political and economic situation of Modern Europe would have an influence on philosophical thought, mainly on ethics and political philosophy.[32]

The scientific revolution also gained legitimacy during this period. Early modern attempts to grapple with the philosophy of infinity focused on and discussed three fundamental disagreements about the infinite—differences that had their origins in the academic philosophical tradition.[33] Philosophers such as Leibniz and Spinoza used this distinction to distinguish God's qualitative infinity from the mathematically abstract concept of infinity.[34] Early modern thinkers differentiated between actual and potential infinity. Academic tradition has traditionally rejected the existence of actual infinities in the created world but has acknowledged potential infinities, following Aristotle's approach to Zeno's paradoxes.[35] Additionally, the advent of early modern thought was linked to changes in the period's intellectual and cultural context, such as the advancement of natural science, theological contradictions within and between the Catholic and Protestant churches, and the growth of the modern nation-state.[36]

Significant thinkers

Reńe Descartes amid philosophical discussion with several philosophers during the early modern philosophical period

Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Berkeley, Hume, Hobbes, and Kant, as well as philosophers such as Hugo Grotius, Pierre Gassendi, Antoine Arnauld, Nicolas Malebranche, Pierre Bayle, Samuel von Pufendorf, and Francis Hutcheson are all recognised as significant figures in early modern philosophy, for their discourses and theories developed throughout the various philosophical periods.

The political philosophy of natural law, developed by John Locke, was a common and significant concept in early modern thought. Natural law evolved into individual rights and subjective claims. Adding to Aristotle's already known philosophy, Locke suggested that the government give its citizens what they believe are fundamental and natural rights.[37] Thomas Hobbes, alternatively, asserted that natural law has a finite scope. Unchecked liberty led to a state of war where everybody struggled for life.[38] Hobbes encapsulated this state of violence in one of philosophy's most famous passages: "And the life of man, solitary, bad, nasty, brutish, and brief".[39] Thomas Hobbes' worldview concentrated on social and political order and how humans could coexist without danger or risk of civil war.[40]

Thomas Hobbes

Hobbes' moral and political theory includes a consideration of natural rights. Hobbes' natural rights notion also included man in a "state of nature". As he saw it, the basic natural (human) right was to use his power, as he will, to preserve his nature, which is to protect his life.[41]

Natural liberty is distinct from universal laws, which Hobbes referred to as precepts, or rules discovered by reason, which ban a man from doing something that will destroy his life or deprives him of the means to retain it.[42]

In Hobbes' view, life comprised just of freedoms and nothing else "Because of that, everyone has the right to anything, even to one another's body. Because of this, though, as long as inherent human rights to every commodity remain in place, there can be no long-term security for anybody."[43]

This would result in the condition called the "war of all against all," in which humans murder, steal, and enslave each other to remain alive. Hobbes theorised that human existence would be lonely, poor, ugly, brutish, and short in a state of chaos generated by unrestricted rights. As such, people would agree to give up many of their basic rights to build a political and civil society. Social contract theory was first articulated using this early argumentation.[44]

Natural or institutional laws are useless without first being established by a sovereign authority. Before you can talk about right and unjust, some coercive authority must compel folks to keep their promises. There is no such coercive force before the establishment of the state.[45] This coercive State would, in Hobbes' view, have the right to confiscate property in return for a guarantee of citizens' safety from one another and from foreign intervention.

According to social contract theory, "inalienable rights" are those rights that can't be relinquished by people to the sovereign.[46] These inherent rights were believed to be law-independent. Only the strongest could use their privileges in the state of nature.[47] Thereby, individuals give up their natural rights to get protection, and thus have the legal rights conferred by the power to do so.[48]

Many historical justifications for slavery and illiberal governance include consensual arrangements to relinquish inherent rights to freedom and self-determination. De facto inalienability arguments supplied the foundation for the anti-slavery movement to argue against all involuntary enslavement, not only slavery explicitly defined as such. An agreement to unlawfully divide a right would be void of law. Similarly, the argument was used by the democratic movement to reject explicit or implicit social covenants of subjection (e.g., pactum subjectionis) that subjugate a people, for example, in Leviathan by Thomas Hobbes. According to Ernst Cassirer:

There is, at least, one right that cannot be ceded or abandoned: the right to personality...They charged the great logician [Hobbes] with a contradiction in terms. If a man could give up his personality he would cease being a moral being. … There is no pactum subjectionis, no act of submission by which man can give up the state of free agent and enslave himself. For by such an act of renunciation he would give up that very character which constitutes his nature and essence: he would lose his humanity.[49]

Influence

Until the twenty-first century, standard accounts of early modern philosophy and traditional survey courses in Anglo-Saxon universities—presented histories dominated by Descartes, Leibniz, Locke, Spinoza, Berkeley, Hume, and Kant.[50]

Early modern theory has significantly impacted many modern developments, one of which is political philosophy. American political philosopher A. John Simmons examined two interrelated transitions in the early modern period. The first is a metaphysical contrast between political naturalism, which holds that human beings are political by birth, and political anti-naturalism, which holds that humankind's natural state is apolitical.[51] The second is the historical shift from "complex, bureaucratic systems with intertwined religious and contractual relationships" to political cultures that "take the form of independent, territorial states".[52] Observing how these transformations occur is important as the ideas advanced by early modern political theorists played an important role in the creation of political institutions that exist today.[53]

The evolution of early modern philosophy has been recognized as inextricably linked to developments in the period's intellectual and cultural environment through important developments in science, the Catholic and Protestant churches, and the rise of the new modern nation state.[54]

Early modern Asian philosophy

Rise of Navya Nyaya in India

Before the beginning of early modern era, Indian philosophy saw dramatic changes and evolution. The Nyaya-Vaisheshika system merged, the old school of Nyāya gradually transformed into Navya-Nyāya system over a period of centuries.[55] The philosopher who led the transformation of philosophy in early modern India was Gangesa (14th century). After facing a severe and fierce skeptical attack by Advaitin philosopher Sriharsha (12th century),[56][57] he wrote his magnum opus, Tattvacintamani, which initiated radical developments in the whole of Indian philosophy, leading scholars to attribute him as the founder of Navya-Nyāya. Tattvacintamani was a highly influential and sophisticated text; it led the previous major work on logic to become insignificant, replaced the chain of commentaries on the text of the Nyāya Sūtras, and became the bedrock upon which new methods and techniques of logic and epistemology could be developed. It also introduced a new language in which logical and philosophical discourse could take place (10th century Nyaya philosopher Udayana observed that natural language possesses intrinsic ambiguity, comparable to developments and reasons to invent new language in modern logic, which also often led to misunderstandings in discourse. He wrote his independent works of the system deviating from traditional style, and scholars believe it led to the foundation of the Navya-Nyāya language.)

The new language tended to remove the ambiguity of natural language and became a medium through which opponents could completely understand the view point of proponents without any gap. The language became so influential that all the philosophical systems adopted it in one way or another (alongside logical techniques). The language also found its popularity among other fields of literature and law. The language's complexity and sophistication were so high that today there is no single complete translation of Tattvacintamani and other major works (given the fact that major texts before it had found their way into translation into Western languages). Matilal and others argue that Indian philosophy must not be overlooked but must be a part of mainstream philosophical discussion. He discards the position of Indian philosophy as merely a museum piece, and considers it a thing to be looked into for deep insights into modern philosophical problems, and for new ways, world views, perspectives or creativity to analyse and understand things.[58][59] There had been efforts to translate a subsection of Tattvacintamani by scholars like Ingall, Potter, etc.,[60] but they faced fierce criticism for being unable to find a good English equivalent to highly complicated and technical terms and sentences, using some Western tools of logic and analysis which failed to understand or represent the intended meaning. Sometimes even the scholars themselves didn't understand the text (and other works).[61] The popularity of Tattvacintamani in India can be measured by the fact that the original work only had 300 pages, but the commentaries upon it amount to about a million pages (with a text completely devoted one line/sentence in inference section).[62] In an attempt to introduce Navya-Nyāya to the study of Indian philosophy and philosophy in general, an entire perception section was translated for the first time in 2020.[63][64] Ganeri said:[65]

I was once asked in an interview for a job in a philosophy department whether I really believed that there were Indian philosophers of the same stature as Kant and Wittgenstein. I answered "yes" and mentioned Gaṅgeśa. Needless to say, none of them had ever heard of him (and I didn’t get the job). Now at last it will be possible literally to ‘throw the book’ at philosophers who want to see proof.

However, Gangesa didn't come without critically examining Tattvacintamani and innovations in logic, language and philosophy. Varanasi, Nabadvipa and Mithila became the cosmopolitan hubs of intellectual discourse in India. There were many major logicians from these regions; one such radical (as scholar[who?] calls him) thinker, philosopher and logician was Raghunatha Siromani, a man of new innovation and insights, without whom the system wouldn't have reached its zenith and the description of Navya-Nyaya would've remained incomplete. Jonardon Ganeri considers him a quite modern philosopher who transformed Indian philosophy for the second time in this period.[66] Despite the critical approach of his system, Gangesa had quite a conservative leaning, but Siromani wasn't the same kind. He wrote a critical commentary on Tattvacintamani known as didhiti and a work on critical examination of his own system. If Gangesa worked on epistemology, Siromani worked on metaphysics. For him, any old idea which didn't fit into the framework of rigorous and robust logic and proof was discarded and rejected at once, and the one which fit was built upon and deeply expanded. Siromani's camp seemed to be a new system within the new.[67] Siromani was the major spike where the Navya system and techniques became very sophisticated and complicated in language and logic, and just like the languages in modern logic, the system became unapproachable, not only by common people but also to the best scholars and philosophers who have learnt from elsewhere. The system was confined to the intellectual environments of Mithila, Varanasi, and Navadvipa only, but still every philosophical system had a reach to it. Ganeri even notes that the ideas of early enlightenment thinkers like Descartes were known to Varanasi pundits in the 17th century.[68] Ganeri says that 16th and 17th-century texts reflect a unique characteristic of Indian modernity that is not present in texts of the colonial era, where the central ideas of both old and new systems could be willingly given up upon critical investigation. Just like the skeptical and new approach of Descartes, Indian thinkers like Siromani started looking at old and new ideas with a different perspective, which tied the past with the future. Gangesa is referred to as via antiqua, whereas Siromani as via moderna.[by whom?] Siromani's camp considered Gangesa to be of the Navya school, but considered Siromani to be of the Navina school (new within the new).[69][70] V. N. Jha argues that the Navya-Nyaya language must also be introduced and adapted in mainstream philosophical and logical discourse. He claims the Navya-Nyaya inference theory is more elaborate and complicated, with less ambiguity.[71][compared to?]

See also

  • Late modern philosophy
  • Phases of modernity

Citations

  1. Jeffrey Tlumak, Classical Modern Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction, Routledge, 2006, p. xi: "[Classical Modern Philosophy] is a guide through the systems of the seven brilliant seventeenth- and eighteenth-century European philosophers most regularly taught in college Modern Philosophy courses".
  2. 2.0 2.1 Richard Schacht, Classical Modern Philosophers: Descartes to Kant, Routledge, 2013, p. 1: "Seven men have come to stand out from all of their counterparts in what has come to be known as the 'modern' period in the history of philosophy (i.e., the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries): Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, Hume and Kant".
  3. Marshall Berman. 1982. All That Is Solid Melts into Air: The Experience of Modernity. New York: Simon and Schuster. ISBN:0-671-24602-X. London: Verso. pp. 16–17. ISBN:0-86091-785-1. Paperback reprint New York: Viking Penguin, 1988. ISBN:0-14-010962-5.
  4. Brian Leiter (ed.), The Future for Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2006, p. 44 n. 2.
  5. Smith, Kurt (2018). "Descartes' Life and Works". in Zalta, Edward N.. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/descartes-works/. Retrieved 2021-05-19. 
  6. Levers, Merry-Jo D. (2013-01-01). "Philosophical Paradigms, Grounded Theory, and Perspectives on Emergence" (in en). SAGE Open 3 (4): 2158244013517243. doi:10.1177/2158244013517243. ISSN 2158-2440. 
  7. Bica, Daian (2020-12-25). "Thinking with Mechanisms: Mechanical Philosophy and Early Modern Science" (in en). Journal of Early Modern Studies 9: 133–141. doi:10.5840/jems2020916. https://www.pdcnet.org/pdc/bvdb.nsf/purchase?openform&fp=jems&id=jems_2020_0009_0001_0133_0141. Retrieved 2021-05-19. 
  8. Garber, Daniel; Rutherford, Donald, eds (2018) (in en-US). Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, Volume VIII. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198829294.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-186788-0. https://oxford.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/oso/9780198829294.001.0001/oso-9780198829294. 
  9. Wu, Kun (December 2016). "The Interaction and Convergence of the Philosophy and Science of Information" (in en). Philosophies 1 (3): 228–244. doi:10.3390/philosophies1030228. 
  10. Garber, Daniel; Rutherford, Donald, eds (2012) (in en-US). Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy Volume VI. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199659593.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-174521-8. https://oxford.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199659593.001.0001/acprof-9780199659593. 
  11. Beatty, Joy E.; Leigh, Jennifer S. A.; Dean, Kathy Lund (2009-02-01). "Philosophy Rediscovered: Exploring the Connections Between Teaching Philosophies, Educational Philosophies, and Philosophy" (in en). Journal of Management Education 33 (1): 99–114. doi:10.1177/1052562907310557. ISSN 1052-5629. https://doi.org/10.1177/1052562907310557. 
  12. Berchielli, Laura (2020). "Introduction: Ideas of Space and Their Relation to Experience in Early Modern Philosophy". in Berchielli, Laura (in en). Empiricist Theories of Space. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. 54. Cham: Springer International Publishing. pp. 1–48. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-57620-2_1. ISBN 978-3-030-57619-6. http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-3-030-57620-2_1. Retrieved 2021-05-19. 
  13. Schmidt, James (January 2006). "What Enlightenment Was, What It Still Might Be, and Why Kant May Have Been Right After All" (in en). American Behavioral Scientist 49 (5): 647–663. doi:10.1177/0002764205282215. ISSN 0002-7642. http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/0002764205282215. 
  14. Nickles, Thomas (2017). "Scientific Revolutions". in Zalta, Edward N.. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/scientific-revolutions/. Retrieved 2021-05-27. 
  15. "Enlightenment". https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/enlightenment. 
  16. Douglass, Robin (2012-10-01). "Montesquieu and Modern Republicanism" (in en). Political Studies 60 (3): 703–719. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.2011.00932.x. ISSN 0032-3217. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2011.00932.x. 
  17. Colilli, Julian (2016). "Jonathan Israel's Enlightenment: The Case of Giambattista Vico". Italica 93 (3): 469–493. ISSN 0021-3020. https://www.jstor.org/stable/44504589. 
  18. Nicolaidis, Efthymios; Delli, Eudoxie; Livanos, Nikolaos; Tampakis, Kostas; Vlahakis, George (2016-09-20). "Science and Orthodox Christianity: An Overview" (in en). Isis 107 (3): 542–566. doi:10.1086/688704. ISSN 0021-1753. PMID 28707856. https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/10.1086/688704. 
  19. Domínguez, Juan Pablo (2017-05-19). "Introduction: Religious toleration in the Age of Enlightenment". History of European Ideas 43 (4): 273–287. doi:10.1080/01916599.2016.1203590. ISSN 0191-6599. 
  20. De Cruz, Helen (2019). "Religion and Science". in Zalta, Edward N.. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/religion-science/. Retrieved 2021-05-27. 
  21. Desai, Vandana; Potter, Rob (2014-03-21) (in en). The Companion to Development Studies. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-05159-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=AO4jAwAAQBAJ&q=enlightenment+and+progression+and+development&pg=PA95. 
  22. Reiss, Julian; Sprenger, Jan (2020). "Scientific Objectivity". in Zalta, Edward N.. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/scientific-objectivity/. Retrieved 2021-05-27. 
  23. Zafirovski, Milan (2011) (in en). The Enlightenment and Its Effects on Modern Society. New York, NY: Springer New York. doi:10.1007/978-1-4419-7387-0. ISBN 978-1-4419-7386-3. http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-1-4419-7387-0. 
  24. Müßig, Ulrike (2018). "A New Order of the Ages. Normativity and Precedence". in Müßig, Ulrike (in en). Reconsidering Constitutional Formation II Decisive Constitutional Normativity: From Old Liberties to New Precedence. Studies in the History of Law and Justice. 12. Cham: Springer International Publishing. pp. 1–97. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-73037-0_1. ISBN 978-3-319-73037-0. 
  25. "Error: no |title= specified when using {{Cite web}}" (in en). https://sydney.primo.exlibrisgroup.com/discovery/fulldisplay?docid=cdi_jstor_primary_43572323&context=PC&vid=61USYD_INST:sydney&lang=en&search_scope=MyInst_and_CI&adaptor=Primo%20Central&tab=Everything&query=any,contains,religious%20turmoil%20in%20europe%20during%20the%20early%20modern%20period&offset=0. 
  26. Collins, Jeffrey R. (2009). "Redeeming the Enlightenment: New Histories of Religious Toleration". The Journal of Modern History 81 (3): 607–636. doi:10.1086/599275. ISSN 0022-2801. https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/599275. 
  27. Draper, Paul (2017). "Atheism and Agnosticism". in Zalta, Edward N.. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/atheism-agnosticism/. Retrieved 2021-05-27. 
  28. "Pastoral Constitution on the Church in the Modern Word-Gaudium et Spes". https://www.vatican.va/archive/hist_councils/ii_vatican_council/documents/vat-ii_cons_19651207_gaudium-et-spes_en.html. 
  29. "D. Rutherford (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy" (in en). Theoria 73 (4): 334–339. 2007. doi:10.1111/j.1755-2567.2007.tb01212.x. ISSN 1755-2567. https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1111/j.1755-2567.2007.tb01212.x. 
  30. Sellars, John (2020). "Renaissance Humanism and Philosophy as a Way of Life" (in en). Metaphilosophy 51 (2–3): 226–243. doi:10.1111/meta.12409. ISSN 1467-9973. 
  31. Ash, Eric H. (2010). "Introduction: Expertise and the Early Modern State". Osiris 25 (1): 1–24. doi:10.1086/657254. ISSN 0369-7827. https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/657254. 
  32. "Hobbes, Thomas: Moral and Political Philosophy | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy" (in en-US). https://iep.utm.edu/hobmoral/. 
  33. Schmitt, C. B.; Skinner, Quentin; Kessler, Eckhard et al., eds (1988). The Cambridge History of Renaissance Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521251044. ISBN 978-0-521-25104-4. https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/cambridge-history-of-renaissance-philosophy/56DCEA40CA07B949448B608C47B2B670. 
  34. Schechtman, Anat (2019-10-01). "Three Infinities in Early Modern Philosophy" (in en). Mind 128 (512): 1117–1147. doi:10.1093/mind/fzy034. ISSN 0026-4423. https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/128/512/1117/5110139. 
  35. Huggett, Nick (2002-04-30). Zeno's Paradoxes. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/paradox-zeno/. 
  36. Spruyt, Hendrik (2002-06-01). "The origins, development, and possible decline of the modern state". Annual Review of Political Science 5 (1): 127–149. doi:10.1146/annurev.polisci.5.101501.145837. ISSN 1094-2939. 
  37. Uzgalis, William (2001-09-02). John Locke. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/locke/. 
  38. Schmaltz, Tad M. (2002) (in en). Radical Cartesianism: The French Reception of Descartes. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-139-43425-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=pIYcUBCOrNgC&q=%28Schmaltz%2C+2002%29+early+modern+philosophy&pg=PP1. 
  39. Lloyd, Sharon A.; Sreedhar, Susanne (2002-02-12). Hobbes's Moral and Political Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/hobbes-moral/. 
  40. Hampton, Jean (1988) (in en). Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-316-58325-8. https://books.google.com/books?id=1M_LCgAAQBAJ&pg=PP1. 
  41. Carmichael, D. J. C. (March 1990). "Hobbes on Natural Right in Society: The Leviathan Account*" (in en). Canadian Journal of Political Science/Revue Canadienne de Science Politique 23 (1): 3–21. doi:10.1017/S0008423900011598. ISSN 1744-9324. https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/canadian-journal-of-political-science-revue-canadienne-de-science-politique/article/abs/hobbes-on-natural-right-in-society-the-leviathan-account/2BDA061BBFAA7069EBEEF31B9F8A9F67. 
  42. Estrada, Fernando (2012). "El Leviathan de Thomas Hobbes (The Leviathan of Thomas Hobbes)" (in en). SSRN Electronic Journal. doi:10.2139/ssrn.2127939. ISSN 1556-5068. http://www.ssrn.com/abstract=2127939. 
  43. McCrudden, Christopher (2008-09-01). "Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights". European Journal of International Law 19 (4): 655–724. doi:10.1093/ejil/chn043. ISSN 0938-5428. 
  44. Minogue, K. R. (October 1970). "The Logic of Leviathan" (in en). Philosophical Books 11 (3): 10–12. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0149.1970.tb00060.x. http://doi.wiley.com/10.1111/j.1468-0149.1970.tb00060.x. 
  45. Skinner, Quentin (1966). "The Ideological Context of Hobbes's Political Thought". The Historical Journal 9 (3): 286–317. doi:10.1017/S0018246X66000014. ISSN 0018-246X. https://www.jstor.org/stable/2637983. 
  46. Scott, John T. (September 2000). "The Sovereignless State and Locke's Language of Obligation" (in en). American Political Science Review 94 (3): 547–561. doi:10.2307/2585830. ISSN 0003-0554. https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/american-political-science-review/article/abs/sovereignless-state-and-lockes-language-of-obligation/DCF01EF56A5FC3D1E8F9D7FAA1B4E174. 
  47. Bruner, Justin P. (2020-03-01). "Locke, Nozick and the state of nature" (in en). Philosophical Studies 177 (3): 705–726. doi:10.1007/s11098-018-1201-9. ISSN 1573-0883. 
  48. Tuckness, Alex (2020). "Locke's Political Philosophy". in Zalta, Edward N.. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/locke-political/. Retrieved 2021-06-02. 
  49. Ellerman, David (September 2010). "Inalienable Rights: A Litmus Test for Liberal Theories of Justice" (in en). Law and Philosophy 29 (5): 571–599. doi:10.1007/s10982-010-9076-8. ISSN 0167-5249. 
  50. Broad, Jacqueline (2020-10-21). "Early Modern Philosophy: A Perverse Thought Experiment" (in en-US). https://blog.apaonline.org/2020/10/21/early-modern-philosophy-a-perverse-thought-experiment/. 
  51. Caro, Mario, 20 /21 Jh [Hrsg ] De; Caro, Mario De; Macarthur, David; Macarthur, Professor David; MacArthur, Douglas (2004) (in en). Naturalism in Question. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-01295-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=cQke-j8oMHUC&pg=PA1. 
  52. "The Making of the Modern World" (in en-US). 2016-12-26. https://www.e-ir.info/2016/12/26/the-making-of-the-modern-world/. 
  53. Brooks, Thom (2013-05-01). "In Defence of Political Theory: Impact and Opportunities" (in en). Political Studies Review 11 (2): 209–215. doi:10.1111/1478-9302.12007. ISSN 1478-9299. 
  54. Loewenstein, David; Shell, Alison (2019-07-03). "Early Modern Literature and England's Long Reformation". Reformation 24 (2): 53–58. doi:10.1080/13574175.2019.1665264. ISSN 1357-4175. 
  55. "3. Sense and Knowledge in Indian Philosophy". Indian and Chinese Philosophy. Peter Lang. 2016. doi:10.3726/978-3-653-06654-8/6. ISBN 978-3-653-06654-8. http://dx.doi.org/10.3726/978-3-653-06654-8/6. Retrieved 2021-07-17. 
  56. Mills, Ethan (2018-09-15). Three Pillars of Skepticism in Classical India: Nagarjuna, Jayarasi, and Sri Harsa. Lexington Books. https://www.amazon.in/Three-Pillars-Skepticism-Classical-India-ebook/dp/B07GQ6GNFY. 
  57. Handiqui, Krishna Kanta (1956). Naisadhacarita of Sriharsa. http://archive.org/details/in.gov.ignca.5338. 
  58. Phillips, Stephen H (2013-04-15). Epistemology in Classical India. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203152386. ISBN 978-1-136-51899-7. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780203152386. 
  59. Matilal, Bimal K. (1971-12-31). Epistemology, Logic, and Grammar in Indian Philosophical Analysis. doi:10.1515/9783110813562. ISBN 978-3-11-081356-2. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/9783110813562. 
  60. Phillips, Stephen (2020). "Gaṅgeśa". in Zalta, Edward N.. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/gangesa/. Retrieved 2021-07-17. 
  61. (in en) Can logic & Critical reasoning remove suffering permanently? - Gaṅgeśa & his Tattva-cintā-maṇi, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Ml5nbtZ62yw, retrieved 2021-11-08 
  62. Annambhaṭṭa; Jha, Vashishtha Narayan (2010) (in en). Tarkasaṅgraha of Annambhaṭṭa: English Translation with Notes. Chinmaya International Foundation Shodha Sansthan. ISBN 978-93-80864-03-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=MS5kMwEACAAJ. 
  63. bloomsbury.com. "Jewel of Reflection on the Truth about Epistemology" (in en). https://www.bloomsbury.com/uk/jewel-of-reflection-on-the-truth-about-epistemology-9781350066533/. 
  64. Phillips, Stephen H.; Tatacharya, N. S. Ramanuja (2004-12-29). Epistemology of Perception: Gangesa's Tattvacintamani. American Institute of Buddhist Studies. ISBN 0-9753734-3-9. 
  65. "Ganeri, Review of Epistemology Of Perception: Gaṅgeśa's Tattvacintāmaṇi, Jewel Of Reflection On The Truth (About Epistemology): The Perception Chapter (Pratyakṣa-khaṇḍa), Transliterated Text, Translation, And Philosophical Commentary. By STEPHEN H. PHILLIPS AND N.S. RAMANUJA TATACHARYA". http://www.columbia.edu/itc/mealac/pollock/sks/papers/Ganeri(review%20of%20Philips).pdf. 
  66. Ganeri, Jonardon (January 2013). "Raghunātha Śiromaṇi and the Origins of Modernity in India (2012)". Nagoya Studies in Indian Culture and Buddhism. https://www.academia.edu/2146175. 
  67. Ganeri, Jonardon (2019). "Analytic Philosophy in Early Modern India". in Zalta, Edward N.. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/early-modern-india/. Retrieved 2021-07-17. 
  68. Ganeri, Jonardon (2011-03-10). The Lost Age of Reason. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:osobl/9780199218745.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-921874-5. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/acprof:osobl/9780199218745.001.0001. 
  69. Phillips, Stephen H. (2015-04-17). Ganeri, Jonardon. ed. "A Defeasibility Theory of Knowledge in Gaṅgeśa". Oxford Handbooks Online. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199314621.013.32. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199314621.013.32. 
  70. Williams, Michael (2016-07-07). Ganeri, Jonardon. ed. "Raghunātha Śiromaṇi and the Examination of the Truth about the Categories". Oxford Handbooks Online. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199314621.013.30. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199314621.013.30. 
  71. Gaṅgeśa; Jha, Vashishtha Narayan (1986) (in en). The logic of the intermediate casual link: containing the Sanskrit text of the Apūrvavāda of the Śabdakhaṇḍa of the Tattvacintāmaṇi of Gaṅgeśa with English translation and introduction. Sri Satguru Publications. ISBN 978-81-7030-102-8. https://books.google.com/books?id=g98MAAAAIAAJ. 


References

  • Ash, E. (2010). Introduction: Expertise and the Early Modern State. Osiris, 25(1), 1-24.
  • Allhoff, F., Martinich, A., & Vaidya, A. (2007). Early modern philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub.
  • Arblaster, P. (2017). Early Modern English Catholicism: Identity, Memory and Counter-Reformation. Reformation, 22(2), 147–148.
  • Beatty, J., Leigh, J., & Dean, K. (2008). Philosophy Rediscovered. Journal Of Management Education, 33(1), 99–114.
  • Bica, D. (2020). Thinking with Mechanisms: Mechanical Philosophy and Early Modern Science. Journal Of Early Modern Studies, 9(1), 133–141.
  • Bojanowski, J. (2017). Thinking about cases: Applying Kant's universal law formula. European Journal Of Philosophy, 26(4), 1253–1268.
  • Broad, J. (2020). Early Modern Philosophy: A Perverse Thought Experiment | Blog of the APA. Retrieved 18 April 2021, from https://blog.apaonline.org/2020/10/21/early-modern-philosophy-a-perverse-thought-experiment/
  • Brooks, T. (2013). In Defence of Political Theory: Impact and Opportunities. Political Studies Review, 11(2), 209–215.
  • Carmichael, D. (1990). Hobbes on Natural Right in Society: The Leviathan Account. Canadian Journal Of Political Science, 23(1), 3-21.
  • Colilli, Julian (2016). "Jonathan Israel's Enlightenment: The Case of Giambattista Vico". Italica. 93 (3): 469–493. ISSN 0021-3020.
  • Dickason, O., & Ellingson, T. (2002). The Myth of the Noble Savage. The Journal Of American History, 88(4), 1499.
  • Domínguez, Juan Pablo (2017-05-19). "Introduction: Religious toleration in the Age of Enlightenment". History of European Ideas. 43 (4): 273–287. doi:10.1080/01916599.2016.1203590. ISSN 0191-6599.
  • Douglass, Robin (2012-10-01). "Montesquieu and Modern Republicanism". Political Studies. 60 (3): 703–719. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.2011.00932.x. ISSN 0032-3217.
  • Desai, Vandana; Potter, Rob (2014-03-21). The Companion to Development Studies. Routledge. ISBN:978-1-134-05159-5.
  • De Cruz, Helen (2019), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), "Religion and Science", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2021-05-27
  • Early Modern Philosophy: Essential Readings with Commentary, ed. by Aloysius Martinich, Fritz Allhoff, Anand Vaidya (2006).
  • Early Modern Philosophy: Mind, Matter, and Metaphysics, ed. by Christia Mercer and Eileen O'Neill (2005).
  • "Enlightenment | Encyclopedia.com". www.encyclopedia.com. Retrieved 2021-05-27.
  • Estrada, F. (2012). El Leviathan de Thomas Hobbes (The Leviathan of Thomas Hobbes). SSRN Electronic Journal.
  • Garber, D., & Nadler, S. (2005). Oxford studies in early modern philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Huggett, N. (2018). Zeno's Paradoxes. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University.
  • Joy, L., Copenhaver, B., & Schmitt, C. (1993). Renaissance Philosophy. The Philosophical Quarterly, 43(173), 537.
  • KATEB, G. (1989). Hobbes and the Irrationality of Politics. Political Theory, 17(3), 355–391. doi:10.1177/0090591789017003001
  • Lærke, M., Smith, J., & Schliesser, E. (2013). Philosophy and its history. London: Oxford University.
  • May, L., & Kavka, G. (1989). Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory. Noûs, 23(4), 560.
  • Matthew Hoye, J. (2019). Natural Justice, Law, and Virtue in Hobbes's Leviathan. Hobbes Studies, 32(2), 179–208.
  • Lenz, M., & Waldow, A. (2013). Contemporary perspectives on early modern philosophy (1st ed., pp. 19–43). Sydney: The University of Sydney.
  • Levers, M. (2013). Philosophical Paradigms, Grounded Theory, and Perspectives on Emergence. SAGE Open, 3(4).
  • Lloyd, S., & Sreedhar, S. (2018). Hobbes's Moral and Political Philosophy. In Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University.
  • Müßig, Ulrike (2018), Müßig, Ulrike (ed.), "A New Order of the Ages. Normativity and Precedence", Reconsidering Constitutional Formation II Decisive Constitutional Normativity: From Old Liberties to New Precedence, Studies in the History of Law and Justice, Cham: Springer International Publishing, pp. 1–97, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-73037-0_1, ISBN:978-3-319-73037-0, retrieved 2021-05-27
  • Mori, N. (2017). David Hume on Morals, Politics, and Society ed. by Angela Coventry and Andrew Valls. Hume Studies, 43(2), 110–112.
  • Murphy, B. (2010). RATIONALISM AND EMPIRICISM: WILL THE DEBATE EVER END?. Think, 9(24), 35–46.
  • Nachtomy, O., & Reed, R. (2019). INFINITY IN EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY. [New York City]: SPRINGER.
  • Nicolaidis, Efthymios; Delli, Eudoxie; Livanos, Nikolaos; Tampakis, Kostas; Vlahakis, George (2016-09-20). "Science and Orthodox Christianity: An Overview". Isis. 107 (3): 542–566. doi:10.1086/688704. ISSN 0021-1753.
  • Nicolas Rasmussen, N.A, & Catherine Wilson, C.W. (1997). "The Invisible World: Early Modern Philosophy And The Invention Of The Microscope.". Contemporary Sociology 25 (1): 123.
  • Nickles, Thomas (2017), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), "Scientific Revolutions", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2021-05-27
  • Nimbalkar, N. (2011). John locke on personal identityFNx08. Mens Sana Monographs, 9(1), 268.
  • Reiss, Julian; Sprenger, Jan (2020), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), "Scientific Objectivity", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2021-05-27
  • Rutherford, D. (2007). The Cambridge companion to early modern philosophy (1st ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Rutherford, D. (2008). D. Rutherford (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, 73(4), 334–339.
  • Salami, M. (2021). Philosophy has to be about more than white men. The Guardian. Retrieved from https://www.theguardian.com/education/commentisfree/2015/mar/23/philosophy-white-men-university-courses
  • Sellars, J. (2020). RENAISSANCE HUMANISM AND PHILOSOPHY AS A WAY OF LIFE. Metaphilosophy, 51(2-3), 226–243.
  • Schmidt, James (2006-01). "What Enlightenment Was, What It Still Might Be, and Why Kant May Have Been Right After All". American Behavioral Scientist. 49 (5): 647–663.
  • Smith, K. (2018). Descartes’ Life and Works. In Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University.
  • Spruyt, H. (2002). THEORIGINS, DEVELOPMENT, ANDPOSSIBLEDECLINE OF THEMODERNSTATE. Annual Review Of Political Science, 5(1), 127–149.
  • Uzgalis, W. (2018). John Locke. In Stanford Encyclopaedia Of Philosophy (2nd ed.). Los Angeles: Stanford University.
  • Wilson, M. (2016). Ideas and Mechanism (2nd ed.). Newark: Princeton University.
  • Wu, K. (2016). The Interaction and Convergence of the Philosophy and Science of Information. Philosophies, 1(3), 228–244.

External links

el:Φιλοσοφία των Νεότερων Χρόνων