Philosophy:Experimental philosophy
Experimental philosophy is an emerging field of philosophical inquiry[1][2][3][4][5] that makes use of empirical data—often gathered through surveys which probe the intuitions of ordinary people—in order to inform research on philosophical questions.[6][7] This use of empirical data is widely seen as opposed to a philosophical methodology that relies mainly on a priori justification, sometimes called "armchair" philosophy, by experimental philosophers.[8][9][10]
Experimental philosophy initially began by focusing on philosophical questions related to intentional action, the putative conflict between free will and determinism, and causal vs. descriptive theories of linguistic reference.[11] However, experimental philosophy has continued to expand to new areas of research.
Disagreement about what experimental philosophy can accomplish is widespread. One claim is that the empirical data gathered by experimental philosophers can have an indirect effect on philosophical questions by allowing for a better understanding of the underlying psychological processes which lead to philosophical intuitions.[12] Others claim that experimental philosophers are engaged in conceptual analysis, but taking advantage of the rigor of quantitative research to aid in that project.[13][14] Finally, some work in experimental philosophy can be seen as undercutting the traditional methods and presuppositions of analytic philosophy.[15] Several philosophers have offered criticisms of experimental philosophy.
History
Though, in early modern philosophy, natural philosophy was sometimes referred to as "experimental philosophy",[16] the field associated with the current sense of the term dates its origins around 2000 when a small number of students experimented with the idea of fusing philosophy to the experimental rigor of psychology.
While the modern philosophical movement Experimental Philosophy began growing around 2000, there are some earlier examples, such as Hewson, 1994[17] and Naess 1938,[18][19] and the use of empirical methods in philosophy far predates the emergence of the recent academic field. Current experimental philosophers claim that the movement is actually a return to the methodology used by many ancient philosophers.[10][12] Further, other philosophers like David Hume, René Descartes and John Locke are often held up as early models of philosophers who appealed to empirical methodology.[5][20]
Areas of research
Consciousness
The questions of what consciousness is, and what conditions are necessary for conscious thought have been the topic of a long-standing philosophical debate. Experimental philosophers have approached this question by trying to get a better grasp on how exactly people ordinarily understand consciousness. For instance, work by Joshua Knobe and Jesse Prinz (2008) suggests that people may have two different ways of understanding minds generally, and Justin Sytsma and Edouard Machery (2009) have written about the proper methodology for studying folk intuitions about consciousness. Bryce Huebner, Michael Bruno, and Hagop Sarkissian (2010)[21] have further argued that the way Westerners understand consciousness differs systematically from the way that East Asians understand consciousness, while Adam Arico (2010)[22] has offered some evidence for thinking that ordinary ascriptions of consciousness are sensitive to framing effects (such as the presence or absence of contextual information). Some of this work has been featured in the Online Consciousness Conference.
Other experimental philosophers have approached the topic of consciousness by trying to uncover the cognitive processes that guide everyday attributions of conscious states. Adam Arico, Brian Fiala, Rob Goldberg, and Shaun Nichols,[23] for instance, propose a cognitive model of mental state attribution (the AGENCY model), whereby an entity's displaying certain relatively simple features (e.g., eyes, distinctive motions, interactive behavior) triggers a disposition to attribute conscious states to that entity. Additionally, Bryce Huebner[24] has argued that ascriptions of mental states rely on two divergent strategies: one sensitive to considerations of an entity's behavior being goal-directed; the other sensitive to considerations of personhood.
Cultural diversity
Following the work of Richard Nisbett, which showed that there were differences in a wide range of cognitive tasks between Westerners and East Asians, Jonathan Weinberg, Shaun Nichols and Stephen Stich (2001) compared epistemic intuitions of Western college students and East Asian college students. The students were presented with a number of cases, including some Gettier cases, and asked to judge whether a person in the case really knew some fact or merely believed it. They found that the East Asian subjects were more likely to judge that the subjects really knew.[25] Later Edouard Machery, Ron Mallon, Nichols and Stich performed a similar experiment concerning intuitions about the reference of proper names, using cases from Saul Kripke's Naming and Necessity (1980). Again, they found significant cultural differences. Each group of authors argued that these cultural variances undermined the philosophical project of using intuitions to create theories of knowledge or reference.[26] However, subsequent studies have consistently failed to replicate Weinberg et al.'s (2001) results for other Gettier cases [27] Indeed, more recent studies have actually been providing evidence for the opposite hypothesis, that people from a variety of different cultures have surprisingly similar intuitions in these cases.[28]
Determinism and moral responsibility
One area of philosophical inquiry has been concerned with whether or not a person can be morally responsible if their actions are entirely determined, e.g., by the laws of Newtonian physics. One side of the debate, the proponents of which are called ‘incompatibilists,’ argue that there is no way for people to be morally responsible for immoral acts if they could not have done otherwise. The other side of the debate argues instead that people can be morally responsible for their immoral actions even when they could not have done otherwise. People who hold this view are often referred to as ‘compatibilists.’ It was generally claimed that non-philosophers were naturally incompatibilist,[29] that is they think that if you couldn't have done anything else, then you are not morally responsible for your action. Experimental philosophers have addressed this question by presenting people with hypothetical situations in which it is clear that a person's actions are completely determined. Then the person does something morally wrong, and people are asked if that person is morally responsible for what she or he did. Using this technique Nichols and Knobe (2007) found that "people's responses to questions about moral responsibility can vary dramatically depending on the way in which the question is formulated"[30] and argue that "people tend to have compatiblist intuitions when they think about the problem in a more concrete, emotional way but that they tend to have incompatiblist intuitions when they think about the problem in a more abstract, cognitive way".[31]
Epistemology
Recent work in experimental epistemology has tested the apparently empirical claims of various epistemological views. For example, research on epistemic contextualism has proceeded by conducting experiments in which ordinary people are presented with vignettes that involve a knowledge ascription.[32][33][34] Participants are then asked to report on the status of that knowledge ascription. The studies address contextualism by varying the context of the knowledge ascription (for example, how important it is that the agent in the vignette has accurate knowledge). Data gathered thus far show no support for what contextualism says about ordinary use of the term "knows".[32][33][34] Other work in experimental epistemology includes, among other things, the examination of moral valence on knowledge attributions (the so-called "epistemic side-effect effect"),[35] of the knowing-that / knowing-how distinction,[36] and of laypeople's intuitions about lying,[37][38] improper assertion,[39][40] and insincerity.[41]
Intentional action
A prominent topic in experimental philosophy is intentional action. Work by Joshua Knobe has especially been influential. "The Knobe Effect", as it is often called, concerns an asymmetry in our judgments of whether an agent intentionally performed an action. It is "one of the first, most important, and most widely studied effects" in experimental philosophy.[42] Knobe (2003a) asked people to suppose that the CEO of a corporation is presented with a proposal that would, as a side effect, affect the environment. In one version of the scenario, the effect on the environment will be negative (it will "harm" it), while in another version the effect on the environment will be positive (it will "help" it). In both cases, the CEO opts to pursue the policy and the effect does occur (the environment is harmed or helped by the policy). However, the CEO only adopts the program because he wants to raise profits; he does not care about the effect that the action will have on the environment. Although all features of the scenarios are held constant—except for whether the side effect on the environment will be positive or negative—a majority of people judge that the CEO intentionally hurt the environment in the one case, but did not intentionally help it in the other.[43] Knobe ultimately argues that the effect is a reflection of a feature of the speakers' underlying concept of intentional action: broadly moral considerations affect whether we judge that an action is performed intentionally. However, his exact views have changed in response to further research.[citation needed]
Experimental jurisprudence
Experimental jurisprudence is an emerging topic in experimental philosophy and legal scholarship that explores the nature of legal phenomena through psychological investigations of legal concepts.[44][45][46] The field departs from traditional analytic legal philosophy in its ambition to elucidate common intuitions in a systematic fashion. Equally, unlike research in legal psychology, experimental jurisprudence emphasises the philosophical implications of its findings, notably, for questions about whether, how, and in what respects, the law's content is a matter of moral perspective. Experimental jurisprudence scholarship has argued that philosophers' appeals to the content of folk legal concepts ought to be tested empirically so that, the ‘big [philosophical] cost of rely[ing]... on… a concept that is distinct from that used by folk’,[47] may be allocated correctly.[48] Whereas some legal theorists have welcomed X-Jur's emergence,[49] others have expressed reservations about the contributions it seeks to make.[50]
Predicting philosophical disagreement
Research suggests that some fundamental philosophical intuitions are related to stable individual differences in personality. Although there are notable limits,[51] philosophical intuitions and disagreements can be predicted by heritable Big Five personality traits and their facets. Extraverts are much more likely to be compatibilists,[52][53] particularly if they are high in “warmth.”[54] Extraverts show larger biases and different patterns of beliefs in the Knobe side effect cases.[53][55] Neuroticism is related to susceptibility to manipulation-style free will arguments.[56] Emotional Stability predicts who will attribute virtues to others.[57][58][59] Openness to experience predicts non-objectivist moral intuitions.[60] The link between personality and philosophical intuitions is independent of cognitive abilities, training, education, and expertise.[54] Similar effects have also been found cross-culturally and in different languages including German[61] and Spanish.
Because the Big Five Personality Traits are highly heritable, some have argued that many contemporary philosophical disputes are likely to persist through the generations. This may mean that some historical philosophical disputes are unlikely to be solved by purely rational, traditional philosophical methods and may require empirical data and experimental philosophy.[62]
Additional research suggests that variance in philosophical tendencies is partly explained in part by differences in thinking styles (e.g., the intuitive or reflective reasoning from Dual Process Theory),[63] even among philosophers.[64] For example, accepting faulty intuitions on reflection tests has predicted belief in god,[65] and disbelieving that scientific theories are true,[66] while correct responses on reflection tests predicts decisions to minimize harm (a la utilitarianism) or avoid causing harm (a la deontology) on the trolley problem.[67] These data suggest that reasoning habits may be related to philosophical thinking. However, it has been difficult to detect a causal connection between reasoning habit and philosophical thinking.[68]
Criticisms
In 2006, J. David Velleman attacked experimental philosophy on the blog Left2Right, prompting a response from its defenders on Brian Leiter's blog.[importance?][citation needed]
Antti Kauppinen (2007) has argued that intuitions will not reflect the content of folk concepts unless they are intuitions of competent concept users who reflect in ideal circumstances and whose judgments reflect the semantics of their concepts rather than pragmatic considerations.[69] Experimental philosophers are aware of these concerns,[70] and acknowledge that they constitute a criticism.
Timothy Williamson (2008) has argued that we should not construe philosophical evidence as consisting of intuitions.[citation needed]
Other experimental philosophers have noted that experimental philosophy often fails to meet basic standards of experimental social science. A great deal of the experiments fail to include enough female participants. Analysis of experimental data is often plagued by improper use of statistics, and reliance on data mining. Others have pointed out that many participants in experimental philosophy studies fail to comprehend the often abstract and complicated materials, and few studies report comprehension checks.[71] Holtzman argues that a number of experimental philosophers are guilty of suppressing evidence. Yet, in lumping together all people's intuitions as those of the 'folk,' critics may be ignoring basic concerns identified by standpoint feminists.
Some research in experimental philosophy is misleading because it examines averaged responses to surveys even though in almost all of the studies in experimental philosophy there have been substantial dissenting minorities. Ignoring individual differences may result in a distorted view of folk intuitions or concepts. This may lead to theoretical and strange fictions about everyday intuitions or concepts that experimental philosophy was designed to avoid akin to creating the fiction that the average human is not a man or a woman, but the average of a man and woman (e.g., the average person has one ovary and one testicle).[72] This criticism is not unique to experimental philosophy but also applies to other sciences such as psychology and chemistry, although experimental philosophers may lack the training to recognize it.
Problem of reproducibility
In a series of studies published in 2012[73][74][75] and later peer-reviewed,[76][77][78] Hamid Seyedsayamdost showed that some of the most famous results in experimental philosophy were not reproducible. This work gave rise to a focused attention on reproducibility in experimental philosophy. Several philosophers have carried out independent replications and to date all have confirmed Seyedsayamdost's results.[79][80][81]
Some of the areas covered in this debate include the instability and malleability of philosophical intuitions, determinism and moral responsibility, cultural diversity, gender differences and socioeconomic diversity. A large amount of research also focused on epistemology as Stephen Stich argued early on that findings reported by him and co-authors suggested that long practiced methods in philosophy had to be discarded, famously noting that in light of their findings a "reasonable conclusion is that philosophy's 2400 year long infatuation with Plato's method has been a terrible mistake."[82] Since publication of Seyedsayamdost's papers, Stich and collaborators have reversed their research direction on this question.[83] The reason for these problems in experimental philosophy is not entirely clear, although a parallel with experimental psychology has been suggested.[84]
At least one recent study, in which a team attempted to replicate various influential studies in experimental philosophy studies, found that roughly 70% of them could be replicated. The reasons for the discrepancy with Seyedsayamdost's original study are not yet known.[85]
References
- ↑ Lackman, Jon. The X-Philes Philosophy meets the real world, Slate, March 2, 2006.
- ↑ Appiah, Anthony. The New New Philosophy, The New York Times , December 9, 2007.
- ↑ Appiah, Anthony. The 'Next Big Thing' in Ideas, National Public Radio, January 3, 2008.
- ↑ Shea, Christopher. Against Intuition , Chronicle of Higher Education, October 3, 2008.
- ↑ 5.0 5.1 Edmonds, David and Warburton, Nigel. Philosophy’s great experiment , Prospect, March 1, 2009
- ↑ The Experimental Philosophy Page
- ↑ Prinz, J. Experimental Philosophy, YouTube September 17, 2007.
- ↑ Knobe, Joshua. What is Experimental Philosophy?. The Philosophers' Magazine, (28) 2004.
- ↑ Knobe, Joshua. Experimental Philosophy , Philosophy Compass (2) 2007.
- ↑ 10.0 10.1 Knobe, Joshua. Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Significance, Philosophical Explorations (10) 2007.
- ↑ Knobe, Joshua. What is Experimental Philosophy? The Philosophers' Magazine (28) 2004.
- ↑ 12.0 12.1 Knobe, Joshua and Nichols, Shaun. An Experimental Philosophy Manifesto, in Knobe & Nichols (eds.) Experimental Philosophy, §2.1. 2008.
- ↑ Lutz, Sebastian. Ideal Language Philosophy and Experiments on Intuitions . Studia Philosophica Estonica 2.2. Special issue: S. Häggqvist and D. Cohnitz (eds.), The Role of Intuitions in Philosophical Methodology , pp. 117–139. 2009
- ↑ Sytsma, Justin (2010). "The proper province of philosophy: Conceptual analysis and empirical investigation". Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (3): 427–445. doi:10.1007/s13164-010-0032-1. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/id/eprint/4806.
- ↑ Machery, Edouard. What are Experimental Philosophers Doing? . Experimental Philosophy (blog) , July 30, 2007.
- ↑ Anstey, P.; Vanzo, A. (2012). "The Origins of Early Modern Experimental Philosophy". Intellectual History Review 22 (4): 499–518.
- ↑ Hewson, C. (1994). Empirical Evidence Regarding the Folk Psychological Concept of Belief. Proceedings of the Sixteenth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, 403-408. Hillsdale, New Jersey. (Atlanta, Georgia).
- ↑ Naess, Arne (1938). 'Truth' as Conceived by Those Who Are Not Professional Philosophers.
- ↑ Chapman, Siobhan (2018-09-03). "The experimental and the empirical: Arne Naess' statistical approach to philosophy". British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (5): 961–981. doi:10.1080/09608788.2017.1336075. ISSN 0960-8788. https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2017.1336075.
- ↑ Peter Anstey, "Is x-phi old hat? ", Early Modern Experimental Philosophy Blog, 30 August 2010.
- ↑ Huebner, B.; Bruno, M.; Sarkissian, H. (2010). "What Does the Nation of China Think about Phenomenal States?". Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (2): 225–243. doi:10.1007/s13164-009-0009-0.
- ↑ Arico, A (2010). "Folk Psychology, Consciousness, and Context Effects". Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (3): 371–393. doi:10.1007/s13164-010-0029-9.
- ↑ Arico, A., Fiala, B., Goldberg, R., and Nichols, S. forthcoming. Mind & Language.
- ↑ Huebner, B (2010). "Commonsense Concepts of Phenomenal Consciousness: Does Anyone Care about Functional Zombies?". Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 9 (1): 133–155. doi:10.1007/s11097-009-9126-6.
- ↑ Weinberg, J., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions. Philosophical Topics 29, pp. 429–460.
- ↑ Machery, E.; Mallon, R.; Nichols, S.; Stich, S. (2004). "Semantics, Cross-Cultural Style". Cognition 92 (3): B1–B12. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2003.10.003. PMID 15019555. http://www.rci.rutgers.edu/~stich/Publications/Papers/SemanticIntuitions.pdf.
- ↑ Kim, M., & Yuan, Y. (2015). No cross-cultural differences in the Gettier car case intuition: A replication study of Weinberg et al. 2001. Episteme, 12(03), 355-361. [1] Seyedsayamdost, H. (2015). On normativity and epistemic intuitions: Failure of replication. Episteme, 12(01), 95-116. [2] Nagel, J. (November 21, 2012). "Intuitions and Experiments: A Defense of the Case Method in Epistemology". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (3): 495–527. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2012.00634.x. https://philpapers.org/rec/NAGIAE.
- ↑ Machery, Edouard; Stich, Stephen; Rose, David; Chatterjee, Amita; Karasawa, Kaori; Struchiner, Noel; Sirker, Smita; Usui, Naoki et al. (2015). "Gettier Across Cultures1". Noûs 51 (3): 645–664. doi:10.1111/nous.12110.
- ↑ Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T. & Turner, J. Surveying Freedom: Folk Intuitions about Free Will and Moral Responsibility . Philosophical Psychology (18) 2005 p.563
- ↑ Nichols, Shaun; Knobe, Joshua (2007). "Moral Responsibility and Determinism: The Cognitive Science of Folk Intuitions". Noûs 41 (4): 663–685. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2007.00666.x. http://pantheon.yale.edu/~jk762/Nichols-Knobe.pdf. (PDF p.2)
- ↑ Phillips, Jonathan, ed (15 August 2010). "X-Phi Page". Yale. http://pantheon.yale.edu/~jk762/xphipage.htm#2007_6. (§Papers on Experimental Philosophy and Metaphilosophy)
- ↑ 32.0 32.1 Phelan, M. Evidence that Stakes Don't Matter for Evidence
- ↑ 33.0 33.1 Feltz, A. & Zarpentine, C. Do You Know More When It Matters Less? Philosophical Psychology.
- ↑ 34.0 34.1 May, Joshua; Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter; Hull, Jay G.; Zimmerman, Aaron (2010). "Practical Interests, Relevant Alternatives, and Knowledge Attributions: an Empirical Study". Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (2): 265–273. doi:10.1007/s13164-009-0014-3. PMID 22558061.
- ↑ Beebe, J. & Buckwalter, W. The Epistemic Side-Effect Effect Mind & Language.
- ↑ Bengson, J.; Moffett, M.; Wright, J.C. (2008). "The Folk on Knowing How". Philosophical Studies 142 (3): 387–401. doi:10.1007/s11098-007-9193-x. http://wrightjj1.people.cofc.edu/philosophy/Folk_on_Knowing_How.pdf.
- ↑ Willemsen, Pascale; Rutschmann, Ronja; Wiegmann, Alex (2017-09-01). "Empirically Investigating the Concept of Lying". Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research 34 (3): 591–609. doi:10.1007/s40961-017-0112-z. ISSN 2363-9962. http://psyarxiv.com/4t7pc/.
- ↑ Wiegmann, Alex; Samland, Jana; Waldmann, Michael R. (May 2016). "Lying despite telling the truth". Cognition 150: 37–42. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2016.01.017. ISSN 0010-0277. PMID 26848734.
- ↑ Kneer, Markus (August 2018). "The norm of assertion: Empirical data". Cognition 177: 165–171. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2018.03.020. ISSN 0010-0277. PMID 29684696. https://philpapers.org/rec/KNETNO-2.
- ↑ Marsili, Neri; Wiegmann, Alex (2021-07-01). "Should I say that? An experimental investigation of the norm of assertion" (in en). Cognition 212: 104657. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2021.104657. ISSN 0010-0277. PMID 33798949.
- ↑ Marsili, Neri (2016-01-01). "Lying by Promising: A Study on Insincere Illocutionary Acts". International Review of Pragmatics 8 (2): 271–313. doi:10.1163/18773109-00802005. ISSN 1877-3109. http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/104810/1/Marsili%20-%20Lying%20by%20promising%20-%20most%20final.pdf.
- ↑ Stich, Stephen P.; Machery, Edouard (2022-01-31). "Demographic Differences in Philosophical Intuition: a Reply to Joshua Knobe" (in en). Review of Philosophy and Psychology 14 (2): 401–434. doi:10.1007/s13164-021-00609-7. ISSN 1878-5166. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-021-00609-7.
- ↑ Knobe, Joshua (2003-07-01). "Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language". Analysis 63 (3): 190–194. doi:10.1093/analys/63.3.190. ISSN 0003-2638. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/63.3.190.
- ↑ Tobia, Kevin (2022). "Experimental Jurisprudence". University of Chicago Law Review 89 (3): 735. https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/uclrev/vol89/iss3/3/.
- ↑ Sommers, Roseanna (2021-07-23). "Experimental jurisprudence" (in en). Science 373 (6553): 394–395. doi:10.1126/science.abf0711. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 34437107. Bibcode: 2021Sci...373..394S. https://www.science.org/doi/10.1126/science.abf0711.
- ↑ Prochownik, Karolina Magdalena (2021). "The experimental philosophy of law: New ways, old questions, and how not to get lost" (in en). Philosophy Compass 16 (12). doi:10.1111/phc3.12791. ISSN 1747-9991. https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/phc3.12791.
- ↑ Plunkett, David (2012). "A Positivist Route for Explaining How Facts Make Law" (in en). Legal Theory 18 (2): 139–207. doi:10.1017/S1352325212000079. ISSN 1469-8048. https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/legal-theory/article/abs/positivist-route-for-explaining-how-facts-make-law/377DF152A35C8A2498C155BF821D2D60.
- ↑ Flanagan, Brian; Hannikainen, Ivar R. (2022-01-02). "The Folk Concept of Law: Law Is Intrinsically Moral" (in en). Australasian Journal of Philosophy 100 (1): 165–179. doi:10.1080/00048402.2020.1833953. ISSN 0004-8402. https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/00048402.2020.1833953.
- ↑ Atiq, Emad (2022). "Disagreement about Law and Morality: Empirical Results and the Meta-Problem of Jurisprudence" (in en-US). https://juris.jotwell.com/disagreement-about-law-and-morality-empirical-results-and-the-meta-problem-of-jurisprudence/.
- ↑ Jiménez, Felipe (2021). "Some Doubts About Folk Jurisprudence: The Case of Proximate Cause". University of Chicago Law Review Online. https://lawreviewblog.uchicago.edu/2021/08/23/jimenez-jurisprudence/.
- ↑ Doris, J. (2005). Lack of Character. New York: Oxford University Press.
- ↑ Feltz, A.; Cokely, E.T. (2009). "Do Judgments about Freedom and Responsibility Depend on Who You Are? Personality Differences in Intuitions about Compatibilism and Incompatibilism". Consciousness and Cognition 18 (1): 342–350. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2008.08.001. PMID 18805023.
- ↑ 53.0 53.1 Feltz, A.; Perez, A.; Harris, M. (2012). "Free will, causes, and decisions: Individual differences in written reports". Journal of Consciousness Studies 19: 166–189.
- ↑ 54.0 54.1 Schulz, E.; Cokely, E.T.; Feltz, A. (2011). "Persistent bias in expert judgments about free will and moral responsibility: A test of the Expertise Defense". Consciousness and Cognition 20 (4): 1722–1731. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2011.04.007. PMID 21596586.
- ↑ Cokely, E.T.; Feltz, A. (2009). "Individual differences, judgment biases, and Theory-of-Mind: Deconstructing the intentional action side effect asymmetry". Journal of Research in Personality 43: 18–24. doi:10.1016/j.jrp.2008.10.007.
- ↑ Feltz, A (2013). "Pereboom and premises: Asking the right questions in the experimental philosophy of free will". Consciousness and Cognition 22 (1): 54–63. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2012.11.007. PMID 23262252.
- ↑ Cokely, E.T.; Feltz, A. (2011). "Virtue in business: Morally better, praiseworthy, trustworthy, and more satisfying". Journal of Organizational Moral Psychology 2: 13–26.
- ↑ Feltz. A., & Cokely, E.T. (in press). Virtue or consequences: The folk against Pure Evaluational Internalism. Philosophical Psychology.
- ↑ Feltz, A., & Cokely, E.T. (2012). The virtues of ignorance. The Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 3, 335-350.
- ↑ Feltz, A., & Cokely, E. T. (2008). The fragmented folk: More evidence of stable individual differences in moral judgments and folk intuitions. In B. C. Love, K. McRae & V. M. Sloutsky (Eds.), Proceedings of the 30th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 1771-1776). Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.
- ↑ Cokely, E.T.; Feltz, A. (2009). "Adaptive variation in judgment and philosophical intuition". Consciousness and Cognition 18: 355–357. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2009.01.001.
- ↑ Feltz, A.; Cokely, E.T. (2012). "The Philosophical Personality Argument". Philosophical Studies 161 (2): 227–246. doi:10.1007/s11098-011-9731-4.
- ↑ Byrd, Nick (2021). "Reflective reasoning & philosophy". Philosophy Compass 16 (11). doi:10.1111/phc3.12786. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12786.
- ↑ Byrd, Nick (2022). "Great Minds do not Think Alike: Philosophers' Views Predicted by Reflection, Education, Personality, and Other Demographic Differences". Review of Philosophy and Psychology 14 (2): 647–684. doi:10.1007/s13164-022-00628-y. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-022-00628-y.
- ↑ Pennycook, Gordon; Ross, Robert M.; Koehler, Derek J.; Fugelsang, Jonathan A. (2016). "Atheists and Agnostics Are More Reflective than Religious Believers: Four Empirical Studies and a Meta-Analysis". PLOS ONE 11 (4): e0153039. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0153039. PMID 27054566. Bibcode: 2016PLoSO..1153039P.
- ↑ Byrd, Nick; Białek, Michał (2021). "Your Health vs. My Liberty: Philosophical beliefs dominated reflection and identifiable victim effects when predicting public health recommendation compliance". Cognition 212: 104649. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2021.104649. PMID 33756152. PMC 8599940. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2021.104649.
- ↑ Byrd, Nick; Conway, Paul (2019). "Not all who ponder count costs: Arithmetic reflection predicts utilitarian tendencies, but logical reflection predicts both deontological and utilitarian tendencies". Cognition 192: 103995. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2019.06.007. PMID 31301587. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2019.06.007.
- ↑ Kneer, Markus; Colaço, David; Alexander, Joshua; Machery, Edouard (2021). "On second thought: A refutation of the reflection defense". Oxford Studies of Experimental Philosophy 4. doi:10.1093/oso/9780192856890.003.0010. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192856890.003.0010.
- ↑ Kauppinen, Antti (2007). "The Rise and Fall of Experimental Philosophy". Philosophical Explorations 10 (2): 95–118. doi:10.1080/13869790701305871. https://philarchive.org/rec/KAUTRA.
- ↑ Sinnott-Armstrong, W. Abstract + Concrete = Paradox , 'in Knobe & Nichols (eds.) Experimental Philosophy, (209-230), 2008.
- ↑ Clark, Cory J.; Winegard, Bo M.; Baumeister, Roy F. (2019). "Forget the Folk: Moral Responsibility Preservation Motives and Other Conditions for Compatibilism". Frontiers in Psychology 10: 215. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2019.00215. PMID 30792683.
- ↑ Feltz, A., & Cokely, E.T., (in press). Predicting philosophical disagreement. Philosophy Compass.
- ↑ Seyedsayamdost, Hamid (2012-10-24). On Gender and Philosophical Intuition: Failure of Replication and Other Negative Results. doi:10.2139/ssrn.2166447.
- ↑ Seyedsayamdost, Hamid (2012-10-29). On Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions: Failure to Detect Differences between Ethnic Groups. doi:10.2139/ssrn.2168530.
- ↑ Seyedsayamdost, Hamid (2012-12-17). On Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions: Failure to Detect Differences between Socioeconomic Groups. doi:10.2139/ssrn.2190525.
- ↑ Seyedsayamdost, Hamid (2015-07-04). "On gender and philosophical intuition: Failure of replication and other negative results". Philosophical Psychology 28 (5): 642–673. doi:10.1080/09515089.2014.893288. ISSN 0951-5089. https://philpapers.org/rec/SEYOGA-2.
- ↑ Seyedsayamdost, Hamid (2015-03-01). "On Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions: Failure of Replication". Episteme 12 (1): 95–116. doi:10.1017/epi.2014.27. ISSN 1742-3600.
- ↑ "Items where Author is "Seyedsayamdost, Hamid" - LSE Theses Online". http://etheses.lse.ac.uk/view/creators/Seyedsayamdost=3AHamid=3A=3A.html.
- ↑ Adleberg, Toni; Thompson, Morgan; Nahmias, Eddy (2014-01-01). "Do Men and Women Have Different Philosophical Intuitions? Further Data". Philosophical Psychology 28 (5): 615–641. doi:10.1080/09515089.2013.878834. https://philpapers.org/rec/ADLDMA.
- ↑ Kim, Minsun; Yuan, Yuan (2015-01-01). "No Cross-Cultural Differences in the Gettier Car Case Intuition: A Replication Study of Weinberg Et Al. 2001". Episteme 12 (3): 355–361. doi:10.1017/epi.2015.17. https://philpapers.org/rec/KIMNCD.
- ↑ Yuan, Yuan; Kim, Minun. "Cross-Cultural Universality of Knowledge Attributions". Review of Philosophy and Psychology. https://philpapers.org/rec/YUACUO.
- ↑ Stich, Stephen (2001-01-01). "Plato's Method Meets Cognitive Science". Free Inquiry 21 (2): 36–38. https://philpapers.org/rec/STIPMM.
- ↑ Machery, Edouard; Stich, Stephen; Rose, David; Chatterjee, Amita; Karasawa, Kaori; Struchiner, Noel; Sirker, Smita; Usui, Naoki et al. (2015-01-01). "Gettier Across Cultures". Noûs 50 (4). https://philpapers.org/rec/MACGAC-4.
- ↑ Alfano, Mark; Loeb, Don (2016-01-01). "Experimental Moral Philosophy". in Zalta, Edward N.. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/experimental-moral/.
- ↑ Cova, Florian; Strickland, Brent; Abatista, Angela; Allard, Aurélien; Andow, James; Attie, Mario; Beebe, James; Berniūnas, Renatas et al. (2018). "Estimating the Reproducibility of Experimental Philosophy". Review of Philosophy and Psychology 12: 9–44. doi:10.1007/s13164-018-0400-9. https://www.zora.uzh.ch/id/eprint/160900/1/Kneer_EstimatingTheReproducibilityOf_2018.pdf.
Further reading
- Bengson, J.; Moffett, M.; Wright, J.C. (2009). "The Folk on Knowing How". Philosophical Studies 142 (3): 387–401. doi:10.1007/s11098-007-9193-x. http://wrightjj1.people.cofc.edu/philosophy/Folk_on_Knowing_How.pdf.
- Buckwalter, W. (2010). "Knowledge Isn’t Closed on Saturday: A Study in Ordinary Language", Review of Philosophy and Psychology (formerly European Review of Philosophy), special issue on Psychology and Experimental Philosophy ed. by Edouard Machery, Tania Lombrozo, & Joshua Knobe, 1 (3):395-406. (link)[yes|permanent dead link|dead link}}]
- Donelson, R.; Hannikainen, I. (2019). Lombrozo, Tania; Knobe, Joshua; Nichols, Shaun. eds. "Fuller and the Folk: The Inner Morality of Law Revisited". Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy 3.
- Feltz, A.; Zarpentine, C. (2010). "Do You Know More When It Matters Less?". Philosophical Psychology 23 (5): 683–706. doi:10.1080/09515089.2010.514572. http://faculty.schreiner.edu/adfeltz/Papers/Know%20more.pdf.
- Kauppinen, A (2007). "The Rise and Fall of Experimental Philosophy". Philosophical Explorations 10 (2): 95–118. doi:10.1080/13869790701305871. http://www.helsinki.fi/~amkauppi/phil/The_Rise_and_Fall_of_Experimental_Philosophy.pdf.
- Knobe, J (2003a). "Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language". Analysis 63 (3): 190–193. doi:10.1093/analys/63.3.190. http://pantheon.yale.edu/~jk762/Side-Effect.pdf.
- Knobe, J (2003b). "Intentional action in folk psychology: An experimental investigation". Philosophical Psychology 16 (2): 309–324. doi:10.1080/09515080307771. http://pantheon.yale.edu/~jk762/IntentionSkill.pdf.
- Knobe, J (2004a). "Intention, Intentional Action and Moral Considerations". Analysis 64 (2): 181–187. doi:10.1093/analys/64.2.181.
- Knobe, J. (2004b). "What is Experimental Philosophy?" The Philosophers' Magazine, 28. (link)
- Knobe, J (2007). "Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Significance". Philosophical Explorations 10 (2): 119–122. doi:10.1080/13869790701305905. http://pantheon.yale.edu/~jk762/phil-significance.pdf.
- Knobe, J. & Nichols, S. (2008). Experimental philosophy. Oxford University Press, USA. (link).
- Knobe, J. and Jesse Prinz. (2008). "Intuitions about Consciousness: Experimental Studies". Phenomenology and Cognitive Science.(link)
- Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and Necessity. Harvard University Press.
- Luetge, C., Rusch, H., Uhl, M. (2014). Experimental Ethics: Toward an Empirical Moral Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan.
- Machery, E.; Mallon, R.; Nichols, S.; Stich, S. (2004). "Semantics, Cross-Cultural Style". Cognition 92 (3): B1–B12. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2003.10.003. PMID 15019555.
- May, Joshua; Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter; Hull, Jay G.; Zimmerman, Aaron (2010). "Practical Interests, Relevant Alternatives, and Knowledge Attributions: an Empirical Study". Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (2): 265–273. doi:10.1007/s13164-009-0014-3. PMID 22558061.
- Nichols, S (2002). "How Psychopaths Threaten Moral Rationalism: Is It Irrational to Be Amoral?". The Monist 85 (2): 285–304. doi:10.5840/monist200285210.
- Nichols, S (2004). "After Objectivity: An Empirical Study of Moral Judgment". Philosophical Psychology 17: 5–28. doi:10.1080/0951508042000202354.
- Nichols, S.; Folds-Bennett, T. (2003). "Are Children Moral Objectivists? Children's Judgments about Moral and Response-Dependent Properties". Cognition 90 (2): B23–32. doi:10.1016/s0010-0277(03)00160-4. PMID 14599758.
- Nichols, S.; Knobe, J. (2007). "Moral Responsibility and Determinism: The Cognitive Science of Folk Intuitions". Noûs 41 (4): 663–685. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2007.00666.x. http://www.unc.edu/~knobe/Nichols-Knobe.pdf.
- Sandis, C (2010). "The Experimental Turn and Ordinary Language". Essays in Philosophy 11 (2): 181–196. doi:10.5840/eip20101125. http://commons.pacificu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1364&context=eip.
- Schaffer, J. & Knobe, J. (2012). "Contrastive Knowledge Surveyed". Noûs. (link), (link)
- Sytsma, J.; Machery, E. (2009). "How to Study Folk Intuitions about Consciousness". Philosophical Psychology 22: 21–35. doi:10.1080/09515080802703653. http://www.unc.edu/~knobe/Sytsma-Machery.pdf.
- Weinberg, J.; Nichols, S.; Stich, S. (2001). "Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions". Philosophical Topics 29: 429–460. doi:10.5840/philtopics2001291/217.
- Williamson, T. (2008). The Philosophy of Philosophy. Wiley-Blackwell.
- Spicer, F. (2009). "The X-philes: Review of Experimental Philosophy, edited by Knobe and Nichols". The Philosophers' Magazine (44): 107. Retrieved 2009-01-08. (link)
External links
- Experimental philosophy at PhilPapers (Edited by Wesley Buckwalter).
- Experimental philosophy at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
- Experimental Philosophy at Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- The Experimental Philosophy Page
- The Experimental Philosophy Blog - with several prominent contemporary philosophers as contributors.
- (As of July 2009, The Experimental Philosophy Page and Blog list around 120 different contributors who are actively involved with research in experimental philosophy.)
- 'Yale's Experimental Philosophy Lab (EPL)
- Experimental Philosophy Society (XPS)
- Arizona's Experimental Philosophy Lab
- Indiana's Experimental Epistemology Lab
- Schreiner's Behavioral Philosophy Lab
- Bristol's Experimental Philosophy Page
- Buffalo's Experimental Epistemology Research Group (EERG)
- Metro Experimental Research Group (MERG)
- Experimental Ethics Lab (EEL, TU München)
- Experimental Philosophical Aesthetics
- Xphilosophy YouTube Channel
- Early Modern Experimental Philosophy Blog (University of Otago, New Zealand)
Original source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Experimental philosophy.
Read more |