Philosophy:Moral psychology
Moral psychology is a field of study in both philosophy and psychology. Historically, the term "moral psychology" was used relatively narrowly to refer to the study of moral development.[1][2] Moral psychology eventually came to refer more broadly to various topics at the intersection of ethics, psychology, and philosophy of mind.[3][4][5] Some of the main topics of the field are moral judgment, moral reasoning, moral sensitivity, moral responsibility, moral motivation, moral identity, moral action, moral development, moral diversity, moral character (especially as related to virtue ethics), altruism, psychological egoism, moral luck, moral forecasting, moral emotion, affective forecasting, and moral disagreement.[6][7]
Today, moral psychology is a thriving area of research spanning many disciplines,[8] with major bodies of research on the biological,[9][10] cognitive/computational[11][12][13] and cultural[14][15] basis of moral judgment and behavior, and a growing body of research on moral judgment in the context of artificial intelligence.[16][17]
History
The origins of moral psychology can be traced back to early philosophical works, largely concerned with moral education, such as by Plato and Aristotle in Ancient Greece,[18][19] as well as from the Buddhist[20] and Confucian traditions.[21][22][23] Empirical studies of moral judgment go back at least as far as the 1890s with the work of Frank Chapman Sharp,[24] coinciding with the development of psychology as a discipline separate from philosophy. Since at least 1894, philosophers and psychologists attempted to empirically evaluate the morality of an individual,[25][26] especially attempting to distinguish adults from children in terms of their judgment, but these efforts failed because they "attempted to quantify how much morality an individual had—a notably contentious idea—rather than understand the individual's psychological representation of morality".[27](p284)
Jonathan Haidt[28](p282)
In most introductory psychology courses, students learn about moral psychology by studying the psychologist Lawrence Kohlberg,[29][30][31] who proposed a highly influential theory of moral development, developed throughout the 1950s and 1960s. This theory was built on Piaget's observation that children develop intuitions about justice that they can later articulate. Kohlberg proposed six stages broken into three categories of moral reasoning that he believed to be universal to all people in all cultures.[32] The increasing sophistication of justice-based reasoning was taken as a sign of development. Moral cognitive development, in turn, was assumed to be a necessary (but not sufficient) condition for moral action.[33]
But researchers using the Kohlberg model found a gap between what people said was most moral and actions they took. In response, Augusto Blasi proposed his self-model[34] that links ideas of moral judgment and action through moral commitment. Those with moral goals central to the self-concept are more likely to take moral action, as they feel a greater obligation to do so. Those who are motivated will attain a unique moral identity.[35]
Following the independent publication of a pair of landmark papers in 2001 (respectively led by Jonathan Haidt and Joshua Greene),[36][37] there was a surge in interest in moral psychology across a broad range of subfields of psychology, with interest shifting away from developmental processes towards a greater emphasis on social, cognitive, affective and neural processes involved in moral judgment.[1][5][38]
Methods
Philosophers, psychologists and researchers from other fields have created various methods for studying topics in moral psychology, with empirical studies dating back to at least the 1890s.[27] The methods used in these studies include moral dilemmas such as the trolley problem,[24][37] structured interviews and surveys as a means to study moral psychology and its development, as well as the use of economic games,[39] neuroimaging,[40] and studies of natural language use.[41]
Interview techniques
In 1963, Lawrence Kohlberg presented an approach to studying differences in moral judgment by modeling evaluative diversity as reflecting a series of developmental stages (à la Jean Piaget). Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development are:[42]
- Obedience and punishment orientation
- Self-interest orientation
- Interpersonal accord and conformity
- Authority and social-order maintaining orientation
- Social contract orientation
- Universal ethical principles
Stages 1 and 2 are combined into a single stage labeled "pre-conventional", and stages 5 and 6 are combined into a single stage labeled "post-conventional" for the same reason; psychologists can consistently categorize subjects into the resulting four stages using the "Moral Judgement Interview" which asks subjects why they endorse the answers they do to a standard set of moral dilemmas.[30]
Survey instruments
Between 1910 and 1930, in the United States and Europe, several morality tests were developed to classify subjects as either fit or unfit to make moral judgments.[27][43] Test-takers would classify or rank standardized lists of personality traits, hypothetical actions, or pictures of hypothetical scenes. As early as 1926, catalogs of personality tests included sections specifically for morality tests, though critics persuasively argued that they merely measured intelligence or awareness of social expectations.[27]
Meanwhile, Kohlberg inspired a new series of morality tests. The Defining Issues Test (dubbed "Neo-Kohlbergian" by its constituents) scores relative preference for post-conventional justifications,[44][45] and the Moral Judgment Test scores consistency of one's preferred justifications.[46][47] Both treat evaluative ability as similar to IQ (hence the single score), allowing categorization by high score vs. low score.
Among the more recently developed survey measures, the Moral Foundations Questionnaire[48] is a widely used survey measure of the five moral intuitions proposed by Moral Foundations Theory: care/harm, fairness/cheating, loyalty/betrayal, authority/subversion, and sanctity/degradation. The questions ask respondents to rate various considerations in terms of how relevant they are to the respondent's moral judgments. The purpose of the questionnaire is to measure the degree to which people rely upon each of the five moral intuitions (which may coexist). The new and improved version of this instrument (i.e., Moral Foundations Questionnaire-2; MFQ-2) was developed in 2023. In this version, Fairness was split to Equality and Proportionality. Hence, the MFQ-2 measures Care, Equality, Proportionality, Loyalty, Authority, and Purity.[49] In addition to survey instruments measuring endorsement of moral foundations, a number of other contemporary survey measures exist relating to other broad taxonomies of moral values,[50][51][52] as well as more specific moral beliefs,[53][54] or concerns.[55][56]
Evolutionary origins
According to Haidt,[28] the belief that morality is not innate was one of the few theoretical commitments uniting many of the prominent psychologists studying morality in the twentieth century (with some exceptions[57][58]). A substantial amount of research in recent decades has focused on the evolutionary origins of various aspects of morality.[59][60][61][62]
In Unto Others: the Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior (1998), Elliott Sober and David Sloan Wilson demonstrated that diverse moralities could evolve through group selection.[63] In particular, they dismantled the idea that natural selection will favor a homogeneous population in which all creatures care only about their own personal welfare and/or behave only in ways which advance their own personal reproduction.[63]
Tim Dean has advanced the more general claim that moral diversity would evolve through frequency-dependent selection because each moral approach is vulnerable to a different set of situations which threatened our ancestors (see also Pragmatic ethics § Moral ecology).[64]
Topics and theories
Moral identity
Moral identity refers to the importance of morality to a person's identity, typically construed as either a trait-like individual difference, or set of chronically accessible schemas.[35][65] Moral identity is theorized to be one of the key motivational forces connecting moral reasoning to moral behavior,[65] as suggested by a 2016 meta-analysis reporting that moral identity is positively (albeit only modestly) associated with moral behavior.[66]
Moral values
Psychologist Shalom Schwartz defines individual values as "conceptions of the desirable that guide the way social actors (e.g.organisational leaders, policymakers, individual persons) select actions, evaluate people an events, and explain their actions and evaluations."[67] Cultural values form the basis for social norms, laws, customs and practices. While individual values vary case by case (a result of unique life experience), the average of these values point to widely held cultural beliefs (a result of shared cultural values).
Kristiansen and Hotte[68] reviewed many research articles regarding people's values and attitudes and whether they guide behavior. With the research they reviewed and their own extension of Ajzen and Fishbein's theory of reasoned action, they conclude that value-attitude-behavior depends on the individual and their moral reasoning. Another issue that Kristiansen and Hotte discovered through their research was that individuals tended to "create" values to justify their reactions to certain situations, which they called the "value justification hypothesis".[68] Their theory is comparable to Jonathan Haidt's social intuitionist theory,[36] where individuals justify their intuitive emotions and actions through post-hoc moral reasoning.
Kristiansen and Hotte also found that independent selves had actions and behaviors that are influenced by their own thoughts and feelings, but Interdependent selves have actions, behaviors and self-concepts that were based on the thoughts and feelings of others. Westerners have two dimensions of emotions, activation and pleasantness. The Japanese have one more, the range of their interdependent relationships. Markus and Kitayama found that these two different types of values had different motives. Westerners, in their explanations, show self-bettering biases. Easterners, on the other hand, tend to focus on "other-oriented" biases.[68]
Moral foundations theory
Moral foundations theory, first proposed in 2004 by Jonathan Haidt and Craig Joseph,[69] attempts to explain the origins of and variation in human moral reasoning on the basis of innate, modular foundations.[70] Notably, moral foundations theory has been used to describe the difference between the moral foundations of political liberals and political conservatives.[71][72] Haidt and Joseph expanded on previous research done by Shweder and his three ethics theory.[69] Shweder's theory consisted of three moral ethics: the ethics of community, autonomy, and divinity.[73] Haidt and Graham took this theory and extended it to discuss the five psychological systems that more specifically make up the three moral ethics theory. These Five Foundations of Morality and their importance vary throughout each culture and construct virtues based on their emphasized foundation. The five psychological foundations are:
- Harm/care, which starts with the sensitivity to signs of suffering in offspring and develops into a general dislike of seeing suffering in others and the potential to feel compassion in response.
- Fairness/reciprocity, which is developed when someone observes or engages in reciprocal interactions. This foundation is concerned with virtues related to fairness and justice.
- Ingroup/loyalty, which constitutes recognizing, trusting, and cooperating with members of one's ingroup as well as being wary of members of other groups.
- Authority/respect, which is how someone navigates in a hierarchal ingroups and communities.
- Purity/sanctity, which stems from the emotion of disgust that guards the body by responding to elicitors that are biologically or culturally linked to disease transmission.
The five foundations theory are both a nativist and cultural-psychological theory. Modern moral psychology concedes that "morality is about protecting individuals" and focuses primarily on issues of justice (harm/care and fairness/reciprocity).[71](p99) Their research found that "justice and related virtues...make up half of the moral world for liberals, while justice-related concerns make up only one fifth of the moral world for conservatives".[71](p99) Liberals value harm/care and fairness/reciprocity significantly more than the other moralities, while conservatives value all five equally. Ownership has also been argued to be a strong candidate to be a moral foundation.[74]
Moral virtues
In 2004, D. Lapsley and D. Narvaez outlined how social cognition explains aspects of moral functioning.[75] Their social cognitive approach to personality has six critical resources of moral personality: cognition, self-processes, affective elements of personality, changing social context, lawful situational variability, and the integration of other literature. Lapsley and Narvaez suggest that moral values and actions stem from more than our virtues and are controlled by a set of self-created schemas (cognitive structures that organize related concepts and integrate past events). They claim that schemas are "fundamental to our very ability to notice dilemmas as we appraise the moral landscape" and that over time, people develop greater "moral expertise".[76]
Triune ethics theory
The triune ethics meta-theory (TEM) has been proposed by Darcia Narvaez as a metatheory that highlights the relative contributions to moral development of biological inheritance (including human evolutionary adaptations), environmental influences on neurobiology, and the role of culture.[77] TET proposes three basic mindsets that shape ethical behavior: self-protectionism (a variety of types), engagement, and imagination (a variety of types that are fueled by protectionism or engagement). A mindset influences perception, affordances, and rhetorical preferences. Actions taken within a mindset become an ethic when they trump other values. Engagement and communal imagination represent optimal human functioning that are shaped by the evolved developmental niche (evolved nest) that supports optimal psychosocial neurobiological development.[78] Based on worldwide anthropological research (e.g., Hewlett and Lamb's Hunter-Gatherer Childhoods), Narvaez uses small-band hunter-gatherers as a baseline for the evolved nest and its effects.
Moral reasoning and development
Moral development and reasoning are two overlapping topics of study in moral psychology that have historically received a great amount of attention, even preceding the influential work of Piaget and Kohlberg.[27] Moral reasoning refers specifically to the study of how people think about right and wrong and how they acquire and apply moral rules.[79] Moral development refers more broadly to age-related changes in thoughts and emotions that guide moral beliefs, judgments and behaviors.[80]
Kohlberg's stage theory
Jean Piaget, in watching children play games, noted how their rationales for cooperation changed with experience and maturation.[81] He identified two stages, heteronomous (morality centered outside the self) and autonomous (internalized morality). Lawerence Kohlberg sought to expand Piaget's work. His cognitive developmental theory of moral reasoning dominated the field for decades. He focused on moral development as one's progression in the capacity to reason about justice. Kohlberg's interview method included hypothetical moral dilemmas or conflicts of interest (most notably, the Heinz dilemma). He proposed six stages and three levels of development (claiming that "anyone who interviewed children about dilemmas and who followed them longitudinally in time would come to our six stages and no others).[82] At the Preconventional level, the first two stages included the punishment-and-obedience orientation and the instrumental-relativist orientation. The next level, the conventional level, included the interpersonal concordance or "good boy – nice girl" orientation, along with the "law and order" orientation. Lastly, the final Postconventional level consisted of the social-contract, legalistic orientation and the universal-ethical-principle orientation.[83] According to Kohlberg, an individual is considered more cognitively mature depending on their stage of moral reasoning, which grows as they advance in education and world experience.
Critics of Kohlberg's approach (such as Carol Gilligan and Jane Attanucci) argue that there is an over-emphasis on justice and an under-emphasis on an additional perspective to moral reasoning, known as the care perspective. The justice perspective draws attention to inequality and oppression, while striving for reciprocal rights and equal respect for all. The care perspective draws attention to the ideas of detachment and abandonment, while striving for attention and response to people who need it. Care Orientation is relationally based. It has a more situational focus that is dependent on the needs of others as opposed to Justice Orientation's objectivity.[84] However, reviews by others have found that Gilligan's theory was not supported by empirical studies since orientations are individual dependent.[85][86] In fact, in neo-Kohlbergian studies with the Defining Issues Test, females tend to get slightly higher scores than males.[87][page needed]
The attachment approach to moral judgment
Aner Govrin's attachment approach to moral judgment[88][89][90] proposes that, through early interactions with the caregiver, the child acquires an internal representation of a system of rules that determine how right/wrong judgments are to be construed, used, and understood. By breaking moral situations down into their defining features, the attachment model of moral judgment outlines a framework for a universal moral faculty based on a universal, innate, deep structure that appears uniformly in the structure of almost all moral judgments regardless of their content.
Moral behaviour
Historically, major topics of study in the domain of moral behavior have included violence and altruism,[91][92] bystander intervention and obedience to authority (e.g., the Milgram experiment[93] and Stanford prison experiment[94]).[1][95] Recent research on moral behavior uses a wide range of methods, including using experience sampling to try and estimate the actual prevalence of various kinds of moral behavior in everyday life.[96][97] Research has also focused on variation in moral behavior over time, through studies of phenomena such as moral licensing.[98][99] Yet other studies focusing on social preferences examine various kinds of resource allocation decisions,[14][100] or use incentivized behavioral experiments to investigate the way people weighted their own interests against other people's when deciding whether to harm others, for example, by examine how willing people are to administer electric shocks to themselves vs. others in exchange for money.[101]
James Rest reviewed the literature on moral functioning and identified at least four components necessary for a moral behavior to take place:[102][103]
- Sensitivity – noticing and interpreting the situation
- Reasoning and making a judgment regarding the best (most moral) option
- Motivation (in the moment but also habitually, such as moral identity)
- Implementation - having the skills and perseverance to carry out the action
Reynolds and Ceranic researched the effects of social consensus on one's moral behavior. Depending on the level of social consensus (high vs. low), moral behaviors will require greater or lesser degrees of moral identity to motivate an individual to make a choice and endorse a behavior. Also, depending on social consensus, particular behaviors may require different levels of moral reasoning.[104]
More recent attempts to develop an integrated model of moral motivation[105] have identified at least six different levels of moral functioning, each of which has been shown to predict some type of moral or pro-social behavior: moral intuitions, moral emotions, moral virtues/vices (behavioral capacities), moral values, moral reasoning, and moral willpower. This social intuitionist model of moral motivation[106] suggests that moral behaviors are typically the product of multiple levels of moral functioning, and are usually energized by the "hotter" levels of intuition, emotion, and behavioral virtue/vice. The "cooler" levels of values, reasoning, and willpower, while still important, are proposed to be secondary to the more affect-intensive processes.
Moral behavior is also studied under the umbrella of personality psychology. Topics within personality psychology include the traits or individual differences underlying moral behavior, such as generativity, self-control, agreeableness, cooperativeness and honesty/humility,[107][108][109] as well as moral change goals,[110] among many other topics.
Regarding interventions aimed at shaping moral behavior, a 2009 meta analysis of business ethics instruction programs found that such programs have only "a minimal impact on increasing outcomes related to ethical perceptions, behavior, or awareness."[111] A 2005 meta analysis[112] suggested that positive affect can at least momentarily increase prosocial behavior (with subsequent meta analyses also showing that prosocial behavior reciprocally increases positive affect in the actor[113][114]).
Value-behavior consistency
In looking at the relations between moral values, attitudes, and behaviors, previous research asserts that there is less correspondence between these three aspects than one might assume.[115] In fact, it seems to be more common for people to label their behaviors with a justifying value rather than having a value beforehand and then acting on it. There are some people that are more likely to act on their personal values: those low in self-monitoring and high in self-consciousness, due to the fact that they are more aware of themselves and less aware of how others may perceive them. Self-consciousness here means being literally more conscious of yourself, not fearing judgement or feeling anxiety from others. Social situations and the different categories of norms can be telling of when people may act in accordance with their values, but this still isn't concrete either. People will typically act in accordance with social, contextual and personal norms, and there is a likelihood that these norms can also follow one's moral values. Though there are certain assumptions and situations that would suggest a major value-attitude-behavior relation, there is not enough research to confirm this phenomenon.
Moral willpower
Building on earlier work by Metcalfe and Mischel on delayed gratification,[116] Baumeister, Miller, and Delaney explored the notion of willpower by first defining the self as being made up of three parts: reflexive consciousness, or the person's awareness of their environment and of himself as an individual; interpersonal being, which seeks to mold the self into one that will be accepted by others; and executive function.[117] They stated, "[T]he self can free its actions from being determined by particular influences, especially those of which it is aware".[118] The three prevalent theories of willpower describe it as a limited supply of energy, as a cognitive process, and as a skill that is developed over time. Research has largely supported that willpower works like a "moral muscle" with a limited supply of strength that may be depleted (a process referred to as Ego depletion), conserved, or replenished, and that a single act requiring much self-control can significantly deplete the "supply" of willpower.[117] While exertion reduces the ability to engage in further acts of willpower in the short term, such exertions actually improve a person's ability to exert willpower for extended periods in the long run.[119] Additional research has been conducted that may cast doubt on the idea of ego-depletion.[120]
Moral intuitions
In 2001, Jonathan Haidt introduced his social intuitionist model which claimed that with few exceptions, moral judgments are made based upon socially derived intuitions. Moral intuitions happen immediately, automatically, and unconsciously, with reasoning largely serving to generate post-hoc rationalizations to justify one's instinctual reactions.[36] He provides four arguments to doubt causal importance of reason. Firstly, Haidt argues that since there is a dual process system in the brain when making automatic evaluations or assessments, this same process must be applicable to moral judgement as well. The second argument, based on research on motivated reasoning, claims that people behave like "intuitive lawyers", searching primarily for evidence that will serve motives for social relatedness and attitudinal coherence. Thirdly, Haidt found that people have post hoc reasoning when faced with a moral situation, this a posteriori (after the fact) explanation gives the illusion of objective moral judgement but in reality is subjective to one's gut feeling. Lastly, research has shown that moral emotion has a stronger link to moral action than moral reasoning, citing Damasio's research on the somatic marker hypothesis and Batson's empathy-altruism hypothesis.[36]
Following the publication of a landmark fMRI study in 2001,[37] Joshua Greene separately proposed his dual process theory of moral judgment, according to which intuitive/emotional and deliberative processes respectively give rise to characteristically deontological and consequentialist moral judgments. A "deontologist" is someone who has rule-based morality that is mainly focused on duties and rights; in contrast, a "consequentialist" is someone who believes that only the best overall consequences ultimately matter.[121]
Moral emotions
Moral emotions are a variety of social emotion that are involved in forming and communicating moral judgments and decisions, and in motivating behavioral responses to one's own and others' moral behavior.[122][123][124] While moral reasoning has been the focus of most study of morality dating all the way back to Plato and Aristotle, the emotive side of morality was historically looked upon with disdain in early moral psychology research.[122] However, in the last 30–40 years, there has been a rise in a new front of research: moral emotions as the basis for moral behavior.[124] This development began with a focus on empathy and guilt, but has since moved on to encompass new scholarship on emotions such as anger, shame, disgust, awe, and elevation. While different moral transgressions have been linked to different emotional reactions, bodily reactions to such transgressions are not too different and can be characterized by some felt activations in the gut area as well as the head area.[125]
Moralization and moral conviction
Moralization, a term introduced to moral psychology by Paul Rozin, refers to the process through which preferences are converted into values.[126][127][128] Relatedly, Linda Skitka and colleagues have introduced the concept of moral conviction, which refers to a "strong and absolute belief that something is right or wrong, moral or immoral."[129][130] According to Skitka's integrated theory of moral conviction (ITMC), attitudes held with moral conviction, known as moral mandates, differ from strong but non-moral attitudes in a number of important ways. Namely, moral mandates derive their motivational force from their perceived universality, perceived objectivity, and strong ties to emotion.[131] Perceived universality refers to the notion that individuals experience moral mandates as transcending persons and cultures; additionally, they are regarded as matters of fact. Regarding association with emotion, ITMC is consistent with Jonathan Haidt's social intuitionist model in stating that moral judgments are accompanied by discrete moral emotions (i.e., disgust, shame, guilt). Importantly, Skitka maintains that moral mandates are not the same thing as moral values. Whether an issue will be associated with moral conviction varies across persons.
One of the main lines of IMTC research addresses the behavioral implications of moral mandates. Individuals prefer greater social and physical distance from attitudinally dissimilar others when moral conviction was high. This effect of moral conviction could not be explained by traditional measures of attitude strength, extremity, or centrality. Skitka, Bauman, and Sargis placed participants in either attitudinally heterogeneous or homogenous groups to discuss procedures regarding two morally mandated issues, abortion and capital punishment. Those in attitudinally heterogeneous groups demonstrated the least amount of goodwill towards other group members, the least amount of cooperation, and the most tension/defensiveness. Furthermore, individuals discussing a morally mandated issue were less likely to reach a consensus compared to those discussing non-moral issues.[132]
Intersections with other fields
Sociological applications
Some research shows that people tend to self-segregate based on moral and political views,[133][134] exaggerate the magnitude of moral disagreements across political divides,[135] and avoid exposure to the opinions of those with opposing political views.[136]
Normative implications
Researchers have begun to debate the implications (if any) moral psychology research has for other subfields of ethics such as normative ethics and meta-ethics.[137][138][139][140][141] For example Peter Singer, citing Haidt's work on social intuitionism and Greene's dual process theory, presented an "evolutionary debunking argument" suggesting that the normative force of our moral intuitions is undermined by their being the "biological residue of our evolutionary history."[142] John Michael Doris discusses the way in which social psychological experiments—such as the Stanford prison experiments involving the idea of situationism—call into question a key component in virtue ethics: the idea that individuals have a single, environment-independent moral character.[143][page needed] As a further example, Shaun Nichols (2004) examines how empirical data on psychopathology suggests that moral rationalism is false.[144][page needed]
Additionally, research in moral psychology is being used to inform debates in applied ethics around moral enhancement.[145][146]
Robotics and artificial intelligence
At the intersection of moral psychology and machine ethics, researchers have begun to study people's views regarding the potentially ethically significant decisions that will be made by self-driving cars.[17][16][147][148]
Mohammad Atari and his colleagues recently examined the moral psychology of the famous chatbot, ChatGPT. These authors asked in their title, "which humans?" — rhetorically pointing out that people should not ask how "human-like" machine morality is, but to which humans it resembles.[149] These authors discovered that Large Language Models (LLMs), especially ChatGPT, tend to echo moral values endorsed by Westerners, as their training datasets originate predominantly from Western, Educated, Industrialized, Rich, and Democratic (WEIRD) societies.[150] This study points out that compared to the global average, people from WEIRD societies are more inclined toward individualism and impersonal prosocial behaviors while showing less traditionalism and group loyalty. The authors further highlighted that societies less aligned with these WEIRD moral values tend to experience greater misalignment with the moral values and outputs of ChatGPT.[151]
See also
- Action
- Agency
- Altruism
- Business ethics
- Character education
- Community psychology
- Descriptive ethics
- Experimental philosophy
- Internalism and externalism §Moral philosophy
- International Society for Justice Research
- List of ethics topics
- Meta-ethics
- Moral luck
- Moral Minds
- Neuroethics
- Neuroeconomics §Social decision making
- Peace psychology
- Personal identity
- Psychological egoism
- Psychology of genocide
- Science of morality
- Social preferences
- Trolley problem
- Value (ethics and social sciences)
Notes
- ↑ 1.0 1.1 1.2 Haidt, Jonathan; Kesebir, Selin (2010). "Morality". in Fiske, S; Gilbert, D; Lindzey, G. Handbook of Social Psychology (5 ed.). Hoboken NJ: Wiley. pp. 797–832. http://courses.washington.edu/ccab/Haidt%20&%20Kesebir%20on%20morality%20-%20HB%20Soc%20Psych%202010.pdf.
- ↑ Lapsley, Daniel K. (1996). Moral Psychology. Developmental psychology series. Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press. ISBN 978-0-8133-3032-7. https://archive.org/details/moralpsychology0000laps.
- ↑ Doris, John; Stich, Stephen (2008), Zalta, Edward N., ed., "Moral Psychology: Empirical Approaches", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-psych-emp/
- ↑ Wallace, R. Jay (November 29, 2007). "Moral Psychology". in Jackson, Frank. The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy. OUP Oxford. pp. 86–113. ISBN 978-0-19-923476-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=H4sIErz7KUcC&pg=PA86. "Moral psychology is the study of morality in its psychological dimensions"
- ↑ 5.0 5.1 Ellemers, Naomi; van der Toorn, Jojanneke; Paunov, Yavor; van Leeuwen, Thed (18 January 2019). "The Psychology of Morality: A Review and Analysis of Empirical Studies Published From 1940 Through 2017" (in en). Personality and Social Psychology Review 23 (4): 332–366. doi:10.1177/1088868318811759. ISSN 1088-8683. PMID 30658545.
- ↑ Doris & Stich 2008, §1.
- ↑ Teper, R.; Inzlicht, M.; Page-Gould, E. (2011). "Are we more moral than we think?: Exploring the role of affect in moral behavior and moral forecasting". Psychological Science 22 (4): 553–558. doi:10.1177/0956797611402513. PMID 21415242.
- ↑ Doris & Stich (2008), §1.
- ↑ Sevinc, Gunes; Spreng, R. Nathan; Soriano-Mas, Carles (4 February 2014). "Contextual and Perceptual Brain Processes Underlying Moral Cognition: A Quantitative Meta-Analysis of Moral Reasoning and Moral Emotions". PLOS ONE 9 (2): e87427. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0087427. PMID 24503959. Bibcode: 2014PLoSO...987427S.
- ↑ Moll, Jorge; Zahn, Roland; de Oliveira-Souza, Ricardo; Krueger, Frank; Grafman, Jordan (October 2005). "The neural basis of human moral cognition". Nature Reviews Neuroscience 6 (10): 799–809. doi:10.1038/nrn1768. PMID 16276356.
- ↑ Kleiman-Weiner, Max; Saxe, Rebecca; Tenenbaum, Joshua B. (October 2017). "Learning a commonsense moral theory". Cognition 167: 107–123. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2017.03.005. PMID 28351662.
- ↑ Cushman, Fiery (16 July 2013). "Action, Outcome, and Value". Personality and Social Psychology Review 17 (3): 273–292. doi:10.1177/1088868313495594. PMID 23861355.
- ↑ Crockett, Molly J. (August 2013). "Models of morality". Trends in Cognitive Sciences 17 (8): 363–366. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2013.06.005. PMID 23845564.
- ↑ 14.0 14.1 Henrich, Joseph; Boyd, Robert; Bowles, Samuel; Camerer, Colin; Fehr, Ernst; Gintis, Herbert; McElreath, Richard; Alvard, Michael et al. (22 December 2005). ""Economic man" in cross-cultural perspective: Behavioral experiments in 15 small-scale societies". Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (6): 795–815. doi:10.1017/S0140525X05000142. PMID 16372952. https://authors.library.caltech.edu/2278/1/HENbbs05.pdf.
- ↑ Purzycki, Benjamin Grant; Apicella, Coren; Atkinson, Quentin D.; Cohen, Emma; McNamara, Rita Anne; Willard, Aiyana K.; Xygalatas, Dimitris; Norenzayan, Ara et al. (10 February 2016). "Moralistic gods, supernatural punishment and the expansion of human sociality". Nature 530 (7590): 327–330. doi:10.1038/nature16980. PMID 26863190. Bibcode: 2016Natur.530..327P. https://pure.au.dk/ws/files/96835878/nature16980.pdf.
- ↑ 16.0 16.1 Awad, Edmond; Dsouza, Sohan; Kim, Richard; Schulz, Jonathan; Henrich, Joseph; Shariff, Azim; Bonnefon, Jean-François; Rahwan, Iyad (24 October 2018). "The Moral Machine experiment". Nature 563 (7729): 59–64. doi:10.1038/s41586-018-0637-6. PMID 30356211. Bibcode: 2018Natur.563...59A.
- ↑ 17.0 17.1 Bonnefon, J.-F.; Shariff, A.; Rahwan, I. (23 June 2016). "The social dilemma of autonomous vehicles". Science 352 (6293): 1573–1576. doi:10.1126/science.aaf2654. PMID 27339987. Bibcode: 2016Sci...352.1573B.
- ↑ Carr, David (26 August 2014). "Metaphysics and methods in moral enquiry and education: Some old philosophical wine for new theoretical bottles". Journal of Moral Education 43 (4): 500–515. doi:10.1080/03057240.2014.943167.
- ↑ Lewis, Paul (June 2012). "In defence of Aristotle on character: toward a synthesis of recent psychology, neuroscience and the thought of Michael Polanyi". Journal of Moral Education 41 (2): 155–170. doi:10.1080/03057240.2012.668005.
- ↑ Goodman, Charles, "Ethics in Indian and Tibetan Buddhism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2021 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/ethics-indian-buddhism/>.
- ↑ Fengyan *, Wang (December 2004). "Confucian thinking in traditional moral education: key ideas and fundamental features". Journal of Moral Education 33 (4): 429–447. doi:10.1080/0305724042000327984.
- ↑ Murray, Judson B. (December 2012). "Educating human nature: 'nature' and 'nurture' in early Confucian moral education". Journal of Moral Education 41 (4): 509–527. doi:10.1080/03057240.2012.721759.
- ↑ Wei, Tan Tai (January 1990). "Some Confucian Insights and Moral Education". Journal of Moral Education 19 (1): 33–37. doi:10.1080/0305724900190104.
- ↑ 24.0 24.1 Sharp, Frank Chapman (January 1898). "An Objective Study of Some Moral Judgments". The American Journal of Psychology 9 (2): 198–234. doi:10.2307/1411759.
- ↑ May, Mark A.; Hartshorne, Hugh (March 1925). "Objective Methods of Measuring Character". The Pedagogical Seminary and Journal of Genetic Psychology 32 (1): 45–67. doi:10.1080/08856559.1925.10532317.
- ↑ Pittel, Stephen M.; Mendelsohn, Gerald A. (1966). "Measurement of moral values: A review and critique.". Psychological Bulletin 66 (1): 22–35. doi:10.1037/h0023425. PMID 5329602.
- ↑ 27.0 27.1 27.2 27.3 27.4 Wendorf, Craig A (2001). "History of American morality research, 1894–1932". History of Psychology 4 (3): 272–288. doi:10.1037/1093-4510.4.3.272. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/247411256.
- ↑ 28.0 28.1 Haidt, Jonathan (September 2013). "Moral psychology for the twenty-first century". Journal of Moral Education 42 (3): 281–297. doi:10.1080/03057240.2013.817327.
- ↑ Kohlberg, Lawrence (1958). The development of modes of moral thinking and choice in the years 10 to 16 (PhD thesis). Chicago. OCLC 1165315.
- ↑ 30.0 30.1 Colby, Anne; Kohlberg, Lawrence (1987). The Measurement of Moral Judgment. Standard Issue Scoring Manual. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-32565-3.
- ↑ Kohlberg, L. (1969). "Stage and sequence: The cognitive development approach to socialization". in Goslin, David. Handbook of Socialization Theory and Research. Chicago: Rand McNally. pp. 347–480. https://archive.org/details/handbookofsocial0000gosl.
- ↑ Kohlberg, Lawrence (1971-01-31), "1. Stages of moral development as a basis for moral education", in Beck, Clive M; Crittenden, Brian S; Sullivan, Edmund, Moral Education, University of Toronto Press, pp. 23–92, doi:10.3138/9781442656758-004, ISBN 9781442656758
- ↑ Kohlberg, Lawrence; Hersh, Richard H. (1977). "Moral development: A review of the theory". Theory into Practice 16 (2): 53–59. doi:10.1080/00405847709542675.
- ↑ Lapsley, Daniel (2016-09-22). "Moral Self-Identity and the Social-Cognitive Theory of Virtue" (in en). Developing the Virtues. pp. 34–68. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190271466.003.0003. ISBN 978-0-19-027146-6. https://academic.oup.com/book/7321/chapter/152068808.
- ↑ 35.0 35.1 Hardy, S. A.; Carlo, G. (2011). "Moral identity: What is it, how does it develop, and is it linked to moral action?". Child Development Perspectives 5 (3): 212–218. doi:10.1111/j.1750-8606.2011.00189.x. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/229948988.
- ↑ 36.0 36.1 36.2 36.3 Haidt, Jonathan (October 2001). "The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail". Psychological Review 108 (4): 814–834. doi:10.1037/0033-295X.108.4.814. PMID 11699120. http://fitelson.org/confirmation/reasoning_adler_rips.pdf#page=1036.
- ↑ 37.0 37.1 37.2 Greene, J. D.; Sommerville, R Brian; Nystrom, Leigh E; Darley, John M.; Cohen, Jonathan D (14 September 2001). "An fMRI Investigation of Emotional Engagement in Moral Judgment". Science 293 (5537): 2105–2108. doi:10.1126/science.1062872. PMID 11557895. Bibcode: 2001Sci...293.2105G.
- ↑ Cohen Priva, Uriel; Austerweil, Joseph L. (February 2015). "Analyzing the history of Cognition using Topic Models". Cognition 135: 4–9. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2014.11.006. PMID 25497481.
- ↑ Story, Giles W.; Vlaev, Ivo; Metcalfe, Robert D.; Crockett, Molly J.; Kurth-Nelson, Zeb; Darzi, Ara; Dolan, Raymond J. (30 October 2015). "Social redistribution of pain and money". Scientific Reports 5 (1): 15389. doi:10.1038/srep15389. PMID 26515529. Bibcode: 2015NatSR...515389S.
- ↑ Moll, Jorge; de Oliveira-Souza, Ricardo; Eslinger, Paul J.; Bramati, Ivanei E.; Mourão-Miranda, Janaı́na; Andreiuolo, Pedro Angelo; Pessoa, Luiz (1 April 2002). "The Neural Correlates of Moral Sensitivity: A Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging Investigation of Basic and Moral Emotions". The Journal of Neuroscience 22 (7): 2730–2736. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.22-07-02730.2002. PMID 11923438.
- ↑ Sagi, Eyal; Dehghani, Morteza (31 October 2013). "Measuring Moral Rhetoric in Text". Social Science Computer Review 32 (2): 132–144. doi:10.1177/0894439313506837.
- ↑ Kohlberg, Lawrence (1973). "The Claim to Moral Adequacy of a Highest Stage of Moral Judgment". Journal of Philosophy 70 (18): 630–646. doi:10.2307/2025030.
- ↑ Verplaetse, Jan (2008). "Measuring the moral sense: morality tests in continental Europe between 1910 and 1930". Paedagogica Historica 44 (3): 265–286. doi:10.1080/00309230701722721.
- ↑ Rest, James R. (1979). Development in Judging Moral Issues. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. ISBN 978-0-8166-0891-1.
- ↑ Rest, James; Narvaez, Darcia; Bebeau, Muriel; Thoma, Stephen (1999). "A Neo-Kohlbergian Approach: The DIT and Schema Theory". Educational Psychology Review 11 (4): 291–324. doi:10.1023/A:1022053215271.
- ↑ Lind, Georg (1978). "Wie misst man moralisches Urteil? Probleme und alternative Möglichkeiten der Messung eines komplexen Konstrukts". in Portele, G. (in de). Sozialisation und Moral. Weinheim: Beltz. pp. 171–201. ISBN 9783407511348. OCLC 715635639.
- ↑ Lind, Georg (2008). "The meaning and measurement of moral judgment competence: A dual-aspect model". in Fasko, Daniel Jr; Willis, Wayne. Contemporary Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives on Moral Development and Education. Hampton Press. pp. 185–220.
- ↑ Graham, Jesse; Nosek, Brian A.; Haidt, Jonathan; Iyer, Ravi; Koleva, Spassena; Ditto, Peter H. (2011). "Mapping the moral domain.". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 101 (2): 366–385. doi:10.1037/a0021847. PMID 21244182.
- ↑ Atari, Mohammad; Haidt, Jonathan; Graham, Jesse; Koleva, Sena; Stevens, Sean T.; Dehghani, Morteza (November 2023). "Morality beyond the WEIRD: How the nomological network of morality varies across cultures." (in en). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 125 (5): 1157–1188. doi:10.1037/pspp0000470. ISSN 1939-1315. http://doi.apa.org/getdoi.cfm?doi=10.1037/pspp0000470.
- ↑ Curry, Oliver Scott; Jones Chesters, Matthew; Van Lissa, Caspar J. (February 2019). "Mapping morality with a compass: Testing the theory of 'morality-as-cooperation' with a new questionnaire". Journal of Research in Personality 78: 106–124. doi:10.1016/j.jrp.2018.10.008.
- ↑ Janoff-Bulman, Ronnie; Carnes, Nate C. (31 March 2016). "Social Justice and Social Order: Binding Moralities across the Political Spectrum". PLOS ONE 11 (3): e0152479. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0152479. PMID 27031103. Bibcode: 2016PLoSO..1152479J.
- ↑ Guerra, Valeschka M.; Giner-Sorolla, Roger (January 2010). "The Community, Autonomy, and Divinity Scale (CADS): A New Tool for the Cross-Cultural Study of Morality". Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 41 (1): 35–50. doi:10.1177/0022022109348919. https://kar.kent.ac.uk/36650/1/Guerra%20%26%20Giner-Sorolla%20-%20CADS%20manuscript.pdf.
- ↑ Bastian, Brock; Bain, Paul; Buhrmester, Michael D.; Gómez, Ángel; Vázquez, Alexandra; Knight, Clinton G.; Swann, William B. (August 2015). "Moral Vitalism: Seeing Good and Evil as Real, Agentic Forces". Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 41 (8): 1069–1081. doi:10.1177/0146167215589819. PMID 26089349.
- ↑ Ståhl, Tomas; Zaal, Maarten P.; Skitka, Linda J. (16 November 2016). "Moralized Rationality: Relying on Logic and Evidence in the Formation and Evaluation of Belief Can Be Seen as a Moral Issue". PLOS ONE 11 (11): e0166332. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0166332. PMID 27851777. Bibcode: 2016PLoSO..1166332S.
- ↑ Ho, Arnold K.; Sidanius, Jim; Kteily, Nour; Sheehy-Skeffington, Jennifer; Pratto, Felicia; Henkel, Kristin E.; Foels, Rob; Stewart, Andrew L. (December 2015). "The nature of social dominance orientation: Theorizing and measuring preferences for intergroup inequality using the new SDO7 scale.". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 109 (6): 1003–1028. doi:10.1037/pspi0000033. PMID 26479362. http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/88104/1/Ho_et_al_in_press_JPSP_The_Nature_of_Social_Dominance_Orientation.pdf.
- ↑ Duckitt, John; Bizumic, Boris (December 2013). "Multidimensionality of Right-Wing Authoritarian Attitudes: Authoritarianism-Conservatism-Traditionalism: Authoritarianism-Conservatism-Traditionalism". Political Psychology 34 (6): 841–862. doi:10.1111/pops.12022.
- ↑ Petrinovich, Lewis; O'Neill, Patricia; Jorgensen, Matthew (1993). "An empirical study of moral intuitions: Toward an evolutionary ethics.". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 64 (3): 467–478. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.64.3.467.
- ↑ Krebs, Dennis L.; Denton, Kathy; Wark, Gillian (June 1997). "The Forms and Functions of Real-life Moral Decision-making". Journal of Moral Education 26 (2): 131–145. doi:10.1080/0305724970260202.
- ↑ Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, ed (2007). Moral Psychology, Volume 1: The Evolution of Morality: Adaptations and Innateness. 1. A Bradford Book. ISBN 9780262693547. https://mitpress.mit.edu/books/moral-psychology-volume-1.
- ↑ Brosnan, S. F.; de Waal, F. B. M. (18 September 2014). "Evolution of responses to (un)fairness". Science 346 (6207): 1251776. doi:10.1126/science.1251776. PMID 25324394.
- ↑ Tomasello, Michael; Vaish, Amrisha (3 January 2013). "Origins of Human Cooperation and Morality". Annual Review of Psychology 64 (1): 231–255. doi:10.1146/annurev-psych-113011-143812. PMID 22804772.
- ↑ Hare, Brian (3 January 2017). "Survival of the Friendliest: Evolved via Selection for Prosociality". Annual Review of Psychology 68 (1): 155–186. doi:10.1146/annurev-psych-010416-044201. PMID 27732802.
- ↑ 63.0 63.1 Sober, Elliott; Wilson, David Sloan (1998). Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ISBN 9780674930469. OCLC 37761960. https://archive.org/details/untoothersevolut00sobe.
- ↑ Dean, Tim (2012). "Evolution and moral diversity". Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 7. doi:10.4148/biyclc.v7i0.1775.
- ↑ 65.0 65.1 Hardy, Sam A.; Carlo, Gustavo (2011). "Moral Identity". in Schwartz, Seth J.; Luyckx, Koen; Vignoles, Vivian L.. Handbook of identity theory and research. Springer. pp. 495–513. ISBN 978-1-4419-7988-9.
- ↑ Hertz, Steven G.; Krettenauer, Tobias (1 June 2016). "Does Moral Identity Effectively Predict Moral Behavior?: A Meta-Analysis". Review of General Psychology 20 (2): 129–140. doi:10.1037/gpr0000062. https://scholars.wlu.ca/psyc_faculty/112.
- ↑ Schwartz, S. H. (1999). "A Theory of Cultural Values and Some Implications for Work". Applied Psychology: An International Review 48 (1): 23–47. doi:10.1080/026999499377655. http://130.18.86.27/faculty/warkentin/SecurityPapers/Merrill/Schwartz1999_APIR48_1_CulturalValues.pdf.
- ↑ 68.0 68.1 68.2 Kristiansen, Connie M; Hotte, Alan M (1996). "Morality and the self: Implications for the when and how of value-attitude-behavior relations". The Psychology of Values: The Ontario Symposium on Personality and Social Psychology. 8. Erlbaum Hillsdale, NJ. pp. 77–105.
- ↑ 69.0 69.1 Haidt, Jonathan; Craig Joseph (Fall 2004). "Intuitive ethics: how innately prepared intuitions generate culturally variable virtues". Daedalus 133 (4): 55–66. doi:10.1162/0011526042365555. http://faculty.virginia.edu/haidtlab/articles/haidt.joseph.2004.intuitive-ethics.pub035.pdf. Retrieved 2012-10-13.
- ↑ Graham, J.; Haidt, J.; Koleva, S.; Motyl, M.; Iyer, R.; Wojcik, S.; Ditto, P.H. (2013). Moral Foundations Theory: The pragmatic validity of moral pluralism. 47. 55–130. doi:10.1016/b978-0-12-407236-7.00002-4. ISBN 9780124072367. http://www-bcf.usc.edu/~jessegra/papers/GHKMIWD.inpress.MFT.AESP.pdf. Retrieved 2015-01-11.
- ↑ 71.0 71.1 71.2 Haidt, Jonathan; Graham, Jesse (23 May 2007). "When Morality Opposes Justice: Conservatives Have Moral Intuitions that Liberals may not Recognize". Social Justice Research 20 (1): 98–116. doi:10.1007/s11211-007-0034-z.
- ↑ Graham, Jesse; Haidt, Jonathan; Nosek, Brian A. (2009). "Liberals and conservatives rely on different sets of moral foundations". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 96 (5): 1029–1046. doi:10.1037/a0015141. PMID 19379034. http://projectimplicit.net/nosek/papers/GHN2009.pdf.
- ↑ Shweder, Richard; Much, Nancy; Mahapatra, Manamohan; Park, Lawrence (1997). "The "big three" of morality (autonomy, community, divinity) and the "big three" explanations of suffering.". in Brandt, Allan; Rozin, Paul. Morality and Health. Routledge. pp. 119–169.
- ↑ Atari, Mohammad; Haidt, Jonathan (2023-10-10). "Ownership is (likely to be) a moral foundation". The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 46: e326. doi:10.1017/S0140525X2300119X. ISSN 1469-1825. PMID 37813408. https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/37813408/.
- ↑ Lapsley, Daniel K.; Narvaez, Darcia (2004). "A social-cognitive approach to the moral personality". Moral Development, Self, and Identity. Psychology Press. pp. 189–212. ISBN 978-1-135-63233-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=q054AgAAQBAJ&pg=PA189.
- ↑ Lapsley & Narvaez 2004, p. 197.
- ↑ Narvaez, Darcia (March 1, 2008). "Triune ethics: The neurobiological roots of our multiple moralities". New Ideas in Psychology 26 (1): 95–119. doi:10.1016/j.newideapsych.2007.07.008. ISSN 0732-118X. https://www3.nd.edu/~dnarvaez/TriuneEthicsWord.htm.
- ↑ Narvaez, Darcia (2014). Neurobiology and the Development of Human Morality: Evolution, Culture and Wisdom. WWNorton. ISBN 978-0393706550.
- ↑ Pizarro, David A. (2007). "Moral Reasoning". in Baumeister, Roy F; Vohs, Kathleen F. Encyclopedia of Social Psychology. SAGE Publications, Inc.. pp. 591–592. doi:10.4135/9781412956253.n352. ISBN 9781412956253. https://archive.org/details/encyclopediasoci00baum.
- ↑ Barnett, Mark A. (2007). "Moral Development". in Baumeister, Roy F; Vohs, Kathleen D. Encyclopedia of Social Psychology. SAGE Publications, Inc.. pp. 587. doi:10.4135/9781412956253.n349. ISBN 9781412956253. https://archive.org/details/encyclopediasoci00baum.
- ↑ Piaget, Jean (1948). The Moral Judgment of the Child. Free Press. https://www.burmalibrary.org/docs20/Piaget-moral_judgment_of_the_child-en-ocr-tu.pdf.
- ↑ Kohlberg, Lawrence (1984). The Psychology of Moral Development: The Nature and Validity of Moral Stages. Essays on Moral Development. 2. Harper & Row. pp. 195. ISBN 978-0-06-064761-2.
- ↑ Crain, W.C.. "Kohlberg's Stages of Moral Development". Theories of Development. Prentice-Hall. http://faculty.plts.edu/gpence/html/kohlberg.htm.
- ↑ Gilligan, Carol; Attanucci, Jane (1994). "Two Moral Orientations: Gender Differences and Similarities". in Puka, Bill. Moral Development: Caring Voices and Women's Moral Frames. 34. Taylor & Francis. pp. 123–237. ISBN 978-0-8153-1553-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=_OBjzzmUS2oC&pg=PA123.
- ↑ Walker, Lawrence J.; Smetana, Judith (2005). "Gender and Morality". in Killen, Melanie. Handbook of Moral Development. Psychology Press. pp. 93–115. ISBN 978-1-135-61917-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=4CV5AgAAQBAJ&pg=PA93.
- ↑ Jaffee and Hyde (2001)[full citation needed]
- ↑ Rest, James R.; Narvaez, Darcia; Thoma, Stephen J.; Bebeau, Muriel J. (1999). Postconventional Moral Thinking: A Neo-Kohlbergian Approach. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-1-135-70561-9.
- ↑ Govrin, A (2014). "The ABC of moral development: an attachment approach to moral judgment". Frontiers in Psychology 5 (6): 1–14. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00006. PMID 24478739. This article contains quotations from this source, which is available under the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 Unported (CC BY 3.0) license.
- ↑ Govrin, A. (2019). Ethics and attachment - How we make moral judgments. London: Routledge
- ↑ Govrin, A. (2014) "From Ethics of Care to Psychology of Care: Reconnecting Ethics of Care to Contemporary Moral Psychology", Frontiers in Psychology pp. 1-10
- ↑ Staub, Ervin (2003). Psychology of good and evil: why children, adults, and groups help and harm others.. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-511-07031-0.
- ↑ Baumeister, Roy F. (1997). Evil : inside human cruelty and violence. New York: W.H. Freeman. ISBN 9780716735670.
- ↑ Milgram, Stanley (1963). "Behavioral Study of Obedience". Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 67 (4): 371–8. doi:10.1037/h0040525. PMID 14049516. http://content.apa.org/journals/abn/67/4/371.
- ↑ Haney, Craig; Banks, Curtis; Zimbardo, Philip (1972). Interpersonal Dynamics in a Simulated Prison. https://apps.dtic.mil/dtic/tr/fulltext/u2/751041.pdf.
- ↑ Martin, Jack (2016). "Ernest Becker and Stanley Milgram: Twentieth-century students of evil.". History of Psychology 19 (1): 3–21. doi:10.1037/hop0000016. PMID 26640976.
- ↑ Hofmann, W.; Wisneski, D. C.; Brandt, M. J.; Skitka, L. J. (11 September 2014). "Morality in everyday life". Science 345 (6202): 1340–1343. doi:10.1126/science.1251560. PMID 25214626. Bibcode: 2014Sci...345.1340H.
- ↑ Hofmann, Wilhelm; Brandt, Mark J.; Wisneski, Daniel C.; Rockenbach, Bettina; Skitka, Linda J. (30 May 2018). "Moral Punishment in Everyday Life". Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 44 (12): 1697–1711. doi:10.1177/0146167218775075. PMID 29848212. https://pure.uvt.nl/ws/files/25376159/Moral_Punishment_in_Everyday_Life.pdf.
- ↑ Monin, B; Miller, D. T. (2001). "Moral credentials and the expression of prejudice". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 81 (1): 33–43. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.81.1.33. PMID 11474723. http://www.ask-force.org/web/Discourse/Monin-Moral-Credentials-Prejudice-2001.pdf.
- ↑ Blanken, Irene; van de Ven, Niels; Zeelenberg, Marcel (25 February 2015). "A Meta-Analytic Review of Moral Licensing". Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 41 (4): 540–558. doi:10.1177/0146167215572134. PMID 25716992.
- ↑ Peysakhovich, Alexander; Nowak, Martin A.; Rand, David G. (16 September 2014). "Humans display a 'cooperative phenotype' that is domain general and temporally stable". Nature Communications 5 (1): 4939. doi:10.1038/ncomms5939. PMID 25225950. Bibcode: 2014NatCo...5.4939P.
- ↑ Crockett, Molly J.; Kurth-Nelson, Zeb; Siegel, Jenifer Z.; Dayan, Peter; Dolan, Raymond J. (2 December 2014). "Harm to others outweighs harm to self in moral decision making". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 111 (48): 17320–17325. doi:10.1073/pnas.1408988111. PMID 25404350. Bibcode: 2014PNAS..11117320C.
- ↑ Rest, James R (1983). "Morality". Handbook of Child Psychology 3: 556–629.
- ↑ Narváez, Darcia; Rest, James (1995). "The four components of acting morally". Moral Behavior and Moral Development: An Introduction: 385–400. https://www3.nd.edu/~dnarvaez/documents/NARVAEZREST.pdf.
- ↑ Reynolds, Scott J.; Ceranic, Tara L. (2007). "The effects of moral judgment and moral identity on moral behavior: An empirical examination of the moral individual.". Journal of Applied Psychology 92 (6): 1610–1624. doi:10.1037/0021-9010.92.6.1610. ISSN 1939-1854. PMID 18020800. http://www.pauldavidtuff.com/PDF%20Files/Effects_of_Moral_Judgement.pdf.
- ↑ Leffel, G. M. (2008). "Who cares? Generativity and the moral emotions, part 2: A "social intuitionist model" of moral motivation". Journal of Psychology and Theology 36 (3): 182–201. doi:10.1177/009164710803600303.
- ↑ Leffel 2008's model draws heavily on Haidt 2001's social intuitionist model of moral judgment.
- ↑ Baumeister, Roy F.; Juola Exline, Julie (December 1999). "Virtue, Personality, and Social Relations: Self-Control as the Moral Muscle". Journal of Personality 67 (6): 1165–1194. doi:10.1111/1467-6494.00086. PMID 10637991.
- ↑ Thielmann, Isabel; Spadaro, Giuliana; Balliet, Daniel (January 2020). "Personality and prosocial behavior: A theoretical framework and meta-analysis.". Psychological Bulletin 146 (1): 30–90. doi:10.1037/bul0000217. PMID 31841013. https://zenodo.org/record/3731374.
- ↑ McAdams, Dan P.; Mayukha, Ananya (2023-01-28). "Hiding in plain view: An historical perspective on the study of morality in personality psychology" (in en). Journal of Personality: jopy.12808. doi:10.1111/jopy.12808. ISSN 0022-3506. PMID 36648361.
- ↑ Sun, Jessie; Wilt, Joshua; Meindl, Peter; Watkins, Hanne M.; Goodwin, Geoffrey P. (2023-01-18). "How and Why People Want to Be More Moral" (in en). Journal of Personality: jopy.12812. doi:10.1111/jopy.12812. ISSN 0022-3506. PMID 36652292.
- ↑ Waples, Ethan P.; Antes, Alison L.; Murphy, Stephen T.; Connelly, Shane; Mumford, Michael D. (June 2009). "A Meta-Analytic Investigation of Business Ethics Instruction". Journal of Business Ethics 87 (1): 133–151. doi:10.1007/s10551-008-9875-0.
- ↑ Lyubomirsky, Sonja; King, Laura; Diener, Ed (2005). "The Benefits of Frequent Positive Affect: Does Happiness Lead to Success?". Psychological Bulletin 131 (6): 803–855. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.131.6.803. PMID 16351326.
- ↑ Curry, Oliver Scott; Rowland, Lee A.; Van Lissa, Caspar J.; Zlotowitz, Sally; McAlaney, John; Whitehouse, Harvey (May 2018). "Happy to help? A systematic review and meta-analysis of the effects of performing acts of kindness on the well-being of the actor". Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 76: 320–329. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.2018.02.014.
- ↑ Hui, Bryant P. H.; Ng, Jacky C. K.; Berzaghi, Erica; Cunningham-Amos, Lauren A.; Kogan, Aleksandr (3 September 2020). "Rewards of kindness? A meta-analysis of the link between prosociality and well-being.". Psychological Bulletin 146 (12): 1084–1116. doi:10.1037/bul0000298. PMID 32881540.
- ↑ Darnell, Catherine; Gulliford, Liz; Kristjánsson, Kristján; Paris, Panos (2019). "Phronesis and the Knowledge-Action Gap in Moral Psychology and Moral Education: A New Synthesis?". Human Development 62 (3): 101–129. doi:10.1159/000496136. http://nectar.northampton.ac.uk/11799/3/Darnell_etal_KARGER_2019_Phronesis_and_the_Knowledge_Action_Gap_in_Moral_Psychology_and_Moral_Education_A_New_Synthesis.pdf.
- ↑ Metcalfe, J.; Mischel, W. (1999). "A hot/cool-system analysis of delay of gratification: Dynamics of willpower". Psychological Review 106 (1): 3–19. doi:10.1037/0033-295x.106.1.3. PMID 10197361. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/13101564.
- ↑ 117.0 117.1 Baumeister (2005). "Self and volition". in Miller, William. Judeo-Christian Perspectives on Psychology: Human Nature, Motivation, and Change. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. pp. 57–72. ISBN 978-1-59147-161-5.
- ↑ Baumeister 2005, p. 68.
- ↑ Muraven, Mark; Baumeister, Roy F.; Tice, Dianne M. (August 1, 1999). "Longitudinal Improvement of Self-Regulation Through Practice: Building Self-Control Strength Through Repeated Exercise". The Journal of Social Psychology 139 (4): 446–457. doi:10.1080/00224549909598404. ISSN 0022-4545. PMID 10457761. https://www.albany.edu/~muraven/publications/promotion%20files/articles/muraven,%20baumeister,%20&%20tice,%201999.pdf.
- ↑ "Hagger et al (2016) A Multilab Preregistered Replication of the Ego-Depletion Effect.pdf". https://www.dropbox.com/s/c17hie7wh4yaohd/Hagger%20et%20al%20%282016%29%20A%20Multilab%20Preregistered%20Replication%20of%20the%20Ego-Depletion%20Effect.pdf?dl=0.
- ↑ Greene, Joshua (2008). "The secret joke of Kant's Soul". in Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter. Moral Psychology. 3. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. pp. 35–80. ISBN 978-0-262-69355-4. OCLC 750463100.
- ↑ 122.0 122.1 Pizarro, David A. (2007). "Moral Emotions". in Baumeister, Roy F; Vohs, Kathleen D. Encyclopedia of Social Psychology. SAGE Publications, Inc.. pp. 588–589. doi:10.4135/9781412956253.n350. ISBN 9781412956253. https://archive.org/details/encyclopediasoci00baum.
- ↑ Haidt, Jonathan (2003). "The Moral Emotions". in Davidson, Richard. Handbook of Affective Sciences. Oxford University Press. pp. 855. ISBN 978-0-19-512601-3. http://www.gruberpeplab.com/teaching/psych3131_spring2015/documents/4.1_Haidt2003_Moralemotions.pdf.
- ↑ 124.0 124.1 Tangney, June Price; Stuewig, Jeff; Mashek, Debra J. (January 2007). "Moral Emotions and Moral Behavior". Annual Review of Psychology 58 (1): 345–372. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.56.091103.070145. PMID 16953797. PMC 3083636. http://www.its.caltech.edu/~squartz/Tangney.pdf.
- ↑ Atari, Mohammad; Mostafazadeh Davani, Aida; Dehghani, Morteza (February 2020). "Body Maps of Moral Concerns" (in en). Psychological Science 31 (2): 160–169. doi:10.1177/0956797619895284. ISSN 0956-7976. http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/0956797619895284.
- ↑ Rozin, Paul (1999). "The Process of Moralization". Psychological Science 10 (3): 218–221. doi:10.1111/1467-9280.00139.
- ↑ Rozin, Paul; Markwith, Maureen; Stoess, Caryn (6 May 2016). "Moralization and Becoming a Vegetarian: The Transformation of Preferences Into Values and the Recruitment of Disgust". Psychological Science 8 (2): 67–73. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1997.tb00685.x.
- ↑ Rhee, Joshua J.; Schein, Chelsea; Bastian, Brock (25 November 2019). "The what, how, and why of moralization: A review of current definitions, methods, and evidence in moralization research". Social and Personality Psychology Compass 13 (12). doi:10.1111/spc3.12511.
- ↑ Skitka, Linda (2002). "Do the means always justify the ends or do the ends sometimes justify the means? A value protection model of justice". Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 28 (5): 452–461. doi:10.1177/0146167202288003. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/247746696.
- ↑ Skitka, Linda J.; Hanson, Brittany E.; Scott Morgan, G.; Wisneski, Daniel C. (4 January 2021). "The Psychology of Moral Conviction". Annual Review of Psychology 72 (1): annurev–psych–063020-030612. doi:10.1146/annurev-psych-063020-030612. PMID 32886586.
- ↑ Morgan, G. S.; Skitka, L. J. (2011). "Moral conviction". in Christie, Daniel J.. Encyclopedia of Peace Psychology. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4051-9644-4.
- ↑ Skitka, L. J.; Bauman, C.; Sargis, E. (2005). "Moral conviction: Another contributor to attitude strength or something more?". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 88 (6): 895–917. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.88.6.895. PMID 15982112. https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/7e7e/2fb7cf672e00b4ea00b4a75d4eee2fd51f5d.pdf.
- ↑ Haidt, Jonathan; Rosenberg, Evan; Hom, Holly (2003). "Differentiating Diversities: Moral Diversity Is Not Like Other Kinds". Journal of Applied Social Psychology 33 (1): 1–36. doi:10.1111/j.1559-1816.2003.tb02071.x.
- ↑ Motyl, Matt; Iyer, Ravi; Oishi, Shigehiro; Trawalterl, Sophie; Nosek, Brian A. (2014). "How ideological migration geographically segregates groups". Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 51: 1–14. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.2013.10.010. http://psyarxiv.com/25myb/.
- ↑ Graham, Jesse; Nosek, Brian A.; Haidt, Jonathan; Young, Liane (12 December 2012). "The Moral Stereotypes of Liberals and Conservatives: Exaggeration of Differences across the Political Spectrum". PLOS ONE 7 (12): e50092. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0050092. PMID 23251357. Bibcode: 2012PLoSO...750092G.
- ↑ Frimer, Jeremy A.; Skitka, Linda J.; Motyl, Matt (September 2017). "Liberals and conservatives are similarly motivated to avoid exposure to one another's opinions". Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 72: 1–12. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.2017.04.003. http://psyarxiv.com/mqzue/.
- ↑ Kahane, Guy (March 2011). "Evolutionary Debunking Arguments". Noûs 45 (1): 103–125. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2010.00770.x. PMID 21949447.
- ↑ Greene, Joshua (October 2003). "From neural 'is' to moral 'ought': what are the moral implications of neuroscientific moral psychology?". Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4 (10): 846–850. doi:10.1038/nrn1224. PMID 14523384.
- ↑ Greene, Joshua; Cohen, Jonathan (29 November 2004). "For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences 359 (1451): 1775–1785. doi:10.1098/rstb.2004.1546. PMID 15590618.
- ↑ Berker, Selim (September 2009). "The Normative Insignificance of Neuroscience". Philosophy & Public Affairs 37 (4): 293–329. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.2009.01164.x. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:4391332.
- ↑ Nagel, Thomas (2 November 2013). "You Can't Learn About Morality from Brain Scans". The New Republic. https://newrepublic.com/article/115279/joshua-greenes-moral-tribes-reviewed-thomas-nagel.
- ↑ Singer, Peter (October 2005). "Ethics and Intuitions". The Journal of Ethics 9 (3–4): 331–352. doi:10.1007/s10892-005-3508-y.
- ↑ Doris, John M. (2002). Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-316-02549-9.
- ↑ Nichols, Shaun (2004). Sentimental Rules: On the Natural Foundations of Moral Judgment. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-988347-9.
- ↑ Darby, R. Ryan; Pascual-Leone, Alvaro (22 February 2017). "Moral Enhancement Using Non-invasive Brain Stimulation". Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11: 77. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2017.00077. PMID 28275345.
- ↑ Levy, Neil; Douglas, Thomas; Kahane, Guy; Terbeck, Sylvia; Cowen, Philip J.; Hewstone, Miles; Savulescu, Julian (2014). "Are You Morally Modified?: The Moral Effects of Widely Used Pharmaceuticals". Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 21 (2): 111–125. doi:10.1353/ppp.2014.0023. PMID 25892904.
- ↑ Awad, Edmond; Dsouza, Sohan; Bonnefon, Jean-François; Shariff, Azim; Rahwan, Iyad (24 February 2020). "Crowdsourcing moral machines". Communications of the ACM 63 (3): 48–55. doi:10.1145/3339904.
- ↑ De Freitas, Julian; Anthony, Sam E.; Censi, Andrea; Alvarez, George A. (31 July 2020). "Doubting Driverless Dilemmas". Perspectives on Psychological Science 15 (5): 1284–1288. doi:10.1177/1745691620922201. PMID 32735472. http://psyarxiv.com/a36e5/.
- ↑ Atari, Mohammad; Xue, Mona J.; Park, Peter S.; Blasi, Damián Ezequiel; Henrich, Joseph. OSF. doi:10.31234/osf.io/5b26t. https://osf.io/5b26t/. Retrieved 2023-12-10.
- ↑ Henrich, Joseph (2020-09-08) (in English). The WEIRDest People in the World: How the West Became Psychologically Peculiar and Particularly Prosperous. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux. ISBN 978-0-374-17322-7.
- ↑ Bloom, Paul (2023-11-29). "How Moral Can A.I. Really Be?" (in en-US). The New Yorker. ISSN 0028-792X. https://www.newyorker.com/science/annals-of-artificial-intelligence/how-moral-can-ai-really-be. Retrieved 2023-12-10.
References
- Baron, J.; Spranca, M. (1997). "Protected values". Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 70 (1): 1–16. doi:10.1006/obhd.1997.2690. PMID 9236161.
- Batson, Charles Daniel (1991). The Altruism Question: Toward a Social Psychological Answer. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. ISBN 978-0-8058-0245-0.
- Brandt, Allan M. (2004). "Difference and diffusion: Cross-cultural perspectives on the rise of anti-tobacco policies". in Feldman, Eric. Unfiltered: Conflicts Over Tobacco Policy and Public Health. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. pp. 255–380. ISBN 978-0-674-01334-6.
- Govrin, A. (2019). Ethics and attachment - How we make moral judgments. London: Routledge
- Helweg-Larsen, M.; Tobias, M. R.; Cerban, B. M. (2010). "Risk perception and moralization among smokers in the USA and Denmark: A qualitative approach". British Journal of Health Psychology 15 (4): 871–886. doi:10.1348/135910710x490415. PMID 20181322.
- Katz (1997). "Secular Morality". in Brandt, Allan. Morality and Health. New York: Routledge. pp. 295–330. ISBN 978-0-415-91582-3. OCLC 301566214.
- Jones, A.; Fitness, J. (2008). "Moral hypervigilance: The influence of disgust sensitivity in the moral domain". Emotion 8 (5): 613–627. doi:10.1037/a0013435. PMID 18837611.
- McGraw, A.P.; Tetlock, P.E.; Kristel, O.V. (2003). "The limits of fungibility: Relational schemata and the value of things". Journal of Consumer Research 30 (2): 219–229. doi:10.1086/376805. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/24099208.
- Mikhail, John M (2011). Elements of Moral Cognition: Rawls' Linguistic Analogy and the Cognitive Science of Moral and Legal Judgment. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-85578-5. OCLC 741178494.
- "Moral pscyhology". Britannica Concise Encyclopedia. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica. 2007. ISBN 978-1-59339-293-2.
- Narvaez, Darcia (2005). "The neo-Kohlbergian tradition and beyond: schemas, expertise, and character". Nebraska Symposium on Motivation. Nebraska Symposium on Motivation 51: 119–163. ISSN 0146-7875. PMID 16335739. https://www3.nd.edu/~dnarvaez/documents/NarvaezNebraska03.15.04.pdf.
- Narvaez, Darcia (2005). "Integrative Ethical Education". in Killen, Melanie. Handbook of Moral Development. Psychology Press. pp. 703–733. ISBN 978-1-135-61917-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=4CV5AgAAQBAJ&pg=PA703.
- Narvaez, D (2010). "Moral complexity: The fatal attraction of truthiness and the importance of mature moral functioning". Perspectives on Psychological Science 5 (2): 163–181. doi:10.1177/1745691610362351. PMID 26162122. https://www3.nd.edu/~dnarvaez/documents/MoralComplexity2010FINAL.pdf.
- Narvaez, D (2012). "Moral neuroeducation from early life through the lifespan". Neuroethics 5 (2): 145–157. doi:10.1007/s12152-011-9117-5. http://library.allanschore.com/docs/NarvaezMoralNeuroeducation11.pdf. Retrieved 2018-02-08.
- Rozin, P (1999). "The process of moralization". Psychological Science 10 (3): 218–221. doi:10.1111/1467-9280.00139. https://web.sas.upenn.edu/rozin/files/2016/09/MoralizationPS1999-1y8a9bo.pdf.
- Rozin, P.; Lowery, L.; Imada, S.; Haidt, J. (1999). "The CAD triad hypothesis: A mapping between three moral emotions (contempt, anger, disgust) and three moral codes (community, autonomy, divinity)". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 76 (4): 574–586. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.76.4.574. PMID 10234846. http://faculty.virginia.edu/haidtlab/articles/rozin.lowery.1999.moral-emotion-triad-hypothesis.pub012.pdf. Retrieved 2018-02-08.
- Rozin, P.; Markwith, M.; Stoess, C. (1997). "Moralization and becoming a vegetarian: The transformation of preferences into values and the recruitment of disgust". Psychological Science 8 (2): 67–73. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.1997.tb00685.x. http://foodethics.univie.ac.at/fileadmin/user_upload/inst_ethik_wiss_dialog/Rozin__.._1997._Moralization_and_becoming_a_vegetarian_in__psychological_science.pdf.
- Smith, Michael A. (2004). The Moral Problem. Oxford: Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-18941-1. OCLC 451103422.
- Thagard, Paul (2007). "The Moral Psychology of Conflicts of Interest: Insights from Affective Neuroscience". Journal of Applied Philosophy 24 (4): 367–380. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5930.2007.00382.x. http://watarts.uwaterloo.ca/~pthagard/Articles/moral-psych.2007.pdf.
- Wallace, R. Jay (2006). Normativity and the Will: Selected Essays on Moral Psychology and Practical Reason. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-153699-1.
External links
Library resources about Moral psychology |
- Moral Psychology Research Group – with Knobe, Nichols, Doris and others.
- From the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Empathy
- Moral Character
- Moral Motivation
- Moral Psychology: Empirical Approaches
- Moral Responsibility
- From the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Original source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Moral psychology.
Read more |