Division by zero

From HandWiki
Revision as of 15:05, 6 February 2024 by AstroAI (talk | contribs) (simplify)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Short description: Class of mathematical expression
Graph showing the diagrammatic representation of limits tending to infinity
The reciprocal function y = 1/x. As x approaches zero from the right, y tends to infinity. As x approaches zero from the left, y tends to negative infinity.

In mathematics, division by zero, division where the divisor (denominator) is zero, is a unique and problematic special case. Using fraction notation, the general example can be written as [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac a0 }[/math], where [math]\displaystyle{ a }[/math] is the dividend (numerator).

The usual definition of the quotient in elementary arithmetic is the number which yields the dividend when multiplied by the divisor. That is, [math]\displaystyle{ c = \tfrac ab }[/math] is equivalent to [math]\displaystyle{ c \cdot b = a. }[/math] By this definition, the quotient [math]\displaystyle{ q = \tfrac{a}{0} }[/math] is nonsensical, as the product [math]\displaystyle{ q \cdot 0 }[/math] is always [math]\displaystyle{ 0 }[/math] rather than some other number [math]\displaystyle{ a. }[/math] Following the ordinary rules of elementary algebra while allowing division by zero can create a mathematical fallacy, a subtle mistake leading to absurd results. To prevent this, the arithmetic of real numbers and more general numerical structures called fields leaves division by zero undefined, and situations where division by zero might occur must be treated with care. Since any number multiplied by zero is zero, the expression [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{0}{0} }[/math] is also undefined.

Calculus studies the behavior of functions in the limit as their input tends to some value. When a real function involves division by a quantity tending to zero, the output of the function often becomes arbitrarily large, and is said to "tend to infinity", a type of mathematical singularity. For example, the reciprocal function, [math]\displaystyle{ f(x) = \tfrac 1x, }[/math] tends to infinity as [math]\displaystyle{ x }[/math] tends to [math]\displaystyle{ 0 }[/math] from above. When a function involves the quotient of two functions which both tend to zero at the same input, it is called an indeterminate form, as the resulting behavior depends on which functions are being considered.

As an alternative to the common convention of working with fields such as the real numbers and leaving division by zero undefined, it is possible to define the result of division by zero in other ways, resulting in different number systems. For example, the quotient [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{a}{0} }[/math] can be defined to equal zero; it can be defined to equal a new explicit point at infinity, sometimes denoted by the infinity symbol [math]\displaystyle{ \infty }[/math]; or it can be defined to result in signed infinity, with positive or negative sign depending on the sign of the dividend. In these number systems division by zero is no longer a special exception per se, but the point or points at infinity involve their own new types of exceptional behavior.

In computing, an error may result from an attempt to divide by zero. Depending on the context and the type of number involved, dividing by zero may output positive or negative infinity or a special not-a-number value,[1] generate an exception, display an error message, or crash or hang the program.

Elementary arithmetic

The meaning of division

See also: Quotition and partition

The division [math]\displaystyle{ N/D = Q }[/math] can be conceptually interpreted in several ways.[2]

In quotitive division, the dividend [math]\displaystyle{ N }[/math] is imagined to be split up into parts of size [math]\displaystyle{ D }[/math] (the divisor), and the quotient [math]\displaystyle{ Q }[/math] is the number of resulting parts. For example, imagine ten slices of bread are to be made into sandwiches, each requiring two slices of bread. A total of five sandwiches can be made ([math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{10}{2}=5 }[/math]). Now imagine instead that zero slices of bread are required per sandwich (perhaps a lettuce wrap). Arbitrarily many such sandwiches can be made from ten slices of bread, as the bread is irrelevant.[3]

The quotitive concept of division lends itself to calculation by repeated subtraction: dividing entails counting how many times the divisor can be subtracted before the dividend runs out. Because no finite number of subtractions of zero will ever exhaust a non-zero dividend, calculating division by zero in this way never terminates.[4] Such an interminable division-by-zero algorithm is physically exhibited by some mechanical calculators.[5]

In partitive division, the dividend [math]\displaystyle{ N }[/math] is imagined to be split into [math]\displaystyle{ D }[/math] parts, and the quotient [math]\displaystyle{ Q }[/math] is the resulting size of each part. For example, imagine ten cookies are to be divided among two friends. Each friend will receive five cookies ([math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{10}{2}=5 }[/math]). Now imagine instead that the ten cookies are to be divided among zero friends. How many cookies will each friend receive? Since there are no friends, this is an absurdity.[6]

The slope of line in the plane is a ratio of vertical to horizontal coordinate differences. For a vertical line, this is 1 : 0, a kind of division by zero.

In another interpretation, the quotient [math]\displaystyle{ Q }[/math] represents the ratio [math]\displaystyle{ N:D. }[/math][7] For example, a cake recipe might call for ten cups of flour and two cups of sugar, a ratio of [math]\displaystyle{ 10:2 }[/math] or, proportionally, [math]\displaystyle{ 5:1. }[/math] To scale this recipe to larger or smaller quantities of cake, a ratio of flour to sugar proportional to [math]\displaystyle{ 5:1 }[/math] could be maintained, for instance one cup of flour and one-fifth cup of sugar, or fifty cups of flour and ten cups of sugar.[8] Now imagine a sugar-free cake recipe calls for ten cups of flour and zero cups of sugar. The ratio [math]\displaystyle{ 10:0, }[/math] or proportionally [math]\displaystyle{ 1:0, }[/math] is perfectly sensible:[9] it just means that the cake has no sugar. However, the question "How many parts flour for each part sugar?" still has no meaningful numerical answer.

A geometrical appearance of the division-as-ratio interpretation is the slope of a straight line in the Cartesian plane.[10] The slope is defined to be the "rise" (change in vertical coordinate) divided by the "run" (change in horizontal coordinate) along the line. When this is written using the symmetrical ratio notation, a horizontal line has slope [math]\displaystyle{ 0:1 }[/math] and a vertical line has slope [math]\displaystyle{ 1:0. }[/math] However, if the slope is taken to be a single real number then a horizontal line has slope [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac01 = 0 }[/math] while an vertical line has an undefined slope, since in real-number arithmetic the quotient [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac10 }[/math] is undefined.[11] The real-valued slope [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{y}{x} }[/math] of a line through the origin is the vertical coordinate of the intersection between the line and a vertical line at horizontal coordinate [math]\displaystyle{ 1, }[/math] dashed black in the figure. The vertical red and dashed black lines are parallel, so they have no intersection in the plane. Sometimes they are said to intersect at a point at infinity, and the ratio [math]\displaystyle{ 1:0 }[/math] is represented by a new number [math]\displaystyle{ \infty }[/math];[12] see § Projectively extended real line below. Vertical lines are sometimes said to have an "infinitely steep" slope.

Inverse of multiplication

Division is the inverse of multiplication. The division problem [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{6}{3} = {?} }[/math] can be solved by rewriting it as an equivalent equation involving multiplication, [math]\displaystyle{ {?}\times 3 = 6, }[/math] where [math]\displaystyle{ {?} }[/math] represents the same unknown quantity, and then finding the value for which the statement is true; in this case the unknown quantity is [math]\displaystyle{ 2, }[/math] because [math]\displaystyle{ 2\times 3 = 6, }[/math] so therefore [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac63 = 2. }[/math][13]

An analogous problem involving division by zero, [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{6}{0} = {?}, }[/math] requires determining an unknown quantity satisfying [math]\displaystyle{ {?}\times 0 = 6. }[/math] However, any number multiplied by zero is zero rather than six, so there exists no number which can substitute for [math]\displaystyle{ {?} }[/math] to make a true statement.[14]

When the problem is changed to [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{0}{0} = {?}, }[/math] the equivalent multiplicative statement is [math]\displaystyle{ {?}\times 0 = 0 }[/math]; in this case any value can be substituted for the unknown quantity to yield a true statement, so there is no single number which can be assigned as the quotient [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{0}{0}. }[/math]

Because of these difficulties, quotients where the divisor is zero are traditionally taken to be undefined, and division by zero is not allowed.[15][16]

Fallacies

A compelling reason for not allowing division by zero is that allowing it leads to fallacies.

When working with numbers, it is easy to identify an illegal division by zero. For example:

From [math]\displaystyle{ 0\times 1 = 0 }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ 0\times 2 = 0 }[/math] one gets [math]\displaystyle{ 0\times 1 = 0\times 2. }[/math] Cancelling 0 from both sides yields [math]\displaystyle{ 1 = 2 }[/math], a false statement.

The fallacy here arises from the assumption that it is legitimate to cancel 0 like any other number, whereas, in fact, doing so is a form of division by 0.

Using algebra, it is possible to disguise a division by zero[17] to obtain an invalid proof. For example:[18]

Let x = 1. Multiply both sides by x to get [math]\displaystyle{ x = x^2 }[/math]. Subtract 1 from each side to get [math]\displaystyle{ x - 1 = x^2 - 1. }[/math] The right side can be factored, [math]\displaystyle{ x - 1 = (x + 1)(x - 1). }[/math] Dividing both sides by x − 1 yields [math]\displaystyle{ 1 = x + 1. }[/math] Substituting x = 1 yields [math]\displaystyle{ 1 = 2. }[/math]

This is essentially the same fallacious computation as the previous numerical version, but the division by zero was obfuscated because we wrote 0 as x − 1.

Early attempts

The Brāhmasphuṭasiddhānta of Brahmagupta (c. 598–668) is the earliest text to treat zero as a number in its own right and to define operations involving zero.[17] The author could not explain division by zero in his texts: his definition can be easily proven to lead to algebraic absurdities. According to Brahmagupta,

A positive or negative number when divided by zero is a fraction with the zero as denominator. Zero divided by a negative or positive number is either zero or is expressed as a fraction with zero as numerator and the finite quantity as denominator. Zero divided by zero is zero.

In 830, Mahāvīra unsuccessfully tried to correct the mistake Brahmagupta made in his book Ganita Sara Samgraha: "A number remains unchanged when divided by zero."[17]

Historically, one of the earliest recorded references to the mathematical impossibility of assigning a value to [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{a}{0} }[/math] is contained in Anglo-Irish philosopher George Berkeley's criticism of infinitesimal calculus in 1734 in The Analyst ("ghosts of departed quantities").[19]

Calculus

Calculus studies the behavior of functions using the concept of a limit, the value to which a function's output tends as its input tends to some specific value. The notation [math]\displaystyle{ \lim_{x \to c} f(x) = L }[/math] means that the value of the function [math]\displaystyle{ f }[/math] can be made arbitrarily close to [math]\displaystyle{ L }[/math] by choosing [math]\displaystyle{ x }[/math] sufficiently close to [math]\displaystyle{ c. }[/math]

In the case where the limit of the real function [math]\displaystyle{ f }[/math] increases without bound as [math]\displaystyle{ x }[/math] tends to [math]\displaystyle{ c, }[/math] the function is not defined at [math]\displaystyle{ x, }[/math] a type of mathematical singularity. Instead, the function is said to "tend to infinity", denoted [math]\displaystyle{ \lim_{x \to c} f(x) = \infty, }[/math] and its graph has the line [math]\displaystyle{ x=c }[/math] as a vertical asymptote. While such a function is not formally defined for [math]\displaystyle{ x = c, }[/math] and the infinity symbol [math]\displaystyle{ \infty }[/math] in this case does not represent any specific real number, such limits are informally said to "equal infinity". If the value of the function decreases without bound, the function is said to "tend to negative infinity", [math]\displaystyle{ -\infty. }[/math] In some cases a function tends to two different values when [math]\displaystyle{ x }[/math] tends to [math]\displaystyle{ c }[/math] from above ([math]\displaystyle{ x \to c^+ }[/math]) and below ([math]\displaystyle{ x \to c^- }[/math]); such a function has two distinct one-sided limits.[20]

A basic example of an infinite singularity is the reciprocal function, [math]\displaystyle{ f(x) = 1/x, }[/math] which tends to positive or negative infinity as [math]\displaystyle{ x }[/math] tends to [math]\displaystyle{ 0 }[/math]:

[math]\displaystyle{ \lim_{x \to 0^+} \frac1x = +\infty,\qquad \lim_{x \to 0^-} \frac1x = -\infty. }[/math]

In most cases, the limit of a quotient of functions is equal to the quotient of the limits of each function separately,

[math]\displaystyle{ \lim_{x \to c} \frac{f(x)}{g(x)} = \frac{\displaystyle \lim_{x \to c} f(x)}{\displaystyle \lim_{x \to c} g(x)}. }[/math]

However, when a function is constructed by dividing two functions whose separate limits are both equal to [math]\displaystyle{ 0, }[/math] the limit of the result cannot be determined from the separate limits, so this is called an indeterminate form, informally written [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac00. }[/math] Such a limit may equal any real value, may tend to infinity, or may not converge at all, depending on the particular functions. For example, in

[math]\displaystyle{ \lim_{x \to 1} \dfrac{x^2 - 1}{x - 1}, }[/math]

the separate limits of the numerator and denominator are [math]\displaystyle{ 0 }[/math], so we have the indeterminate form [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac00 }[/math], but simplifying the quotient first shows that the limit exists:

[math]\displaystyle{ \lim_{x \to 1} \frac{x^2 - 1}{x - 1} = \lim_{x \to 1} \frac{(x - 1)(x + 1)}{x - 1} = \lim_{x \to 1} (x + 1) = 2. }[/math]

Alternative number systems

Extended real line

The affinely extended real numbers are obtained from the real numbers [math]\displaystyle{ \R }[/math] by adding two new numbers [math]\displaystyle{ +\infty }[/math] and [math]\displaystyle{ -\infty, }[/math] read as "positive infinity" and "negative infinity" respectively, and representing points at infinity. With the addition of [math]\displaystyle{ \pm \infty, }[/math] the concept of a "limit at infinity" can be made to work like a finite limit. When dealing with both positive and negative extended real numbers, the expression [math]\displaystyle{ 1/0 }[/math] is usually left undefined. However, in contexts where only non-negative values are considered, it is often convenient to define [math]\displaystyle{ 1/0 = +\infty }[/math].

Projectively extended real line

The set [math]\displaystyle{ \mathbb{R}\cup\{\infty\} }[/math] is the projectively extended real line, which is a one-point compactification of the real line. Here [math]\displaystyle{ \infty }[/math] means an unsigned infinity or point at infinity, an infinite quantity that is neither positive nor negative. This quantity satisfies [math]\displaystyle{ -\infty = \infty }[/math], which is necessary in this context. In this structure, [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{a}{0} = \infty }[/math] can be defined for nonzero a, and [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{a}{\infty} = 0 }[/math] when a is not [math]\displaystyle{ \infty }[/math]. It is the natural way to view the range of the tangent function and cotangent functions of trigonometry: tan(x) approaches the single point at infinity as x approaches either +π/2 or π/2 from either direction.

This definition leads to many interesting results. However, the resulting algebraic structure is not a field, and should not be expected to behave like one. For example, [math]\displaystyle{ \infty+\infty }[/math] is undefined in this extension of the real line.

Riemann sphere

The subject of complex analysis applies the concepts of calculus in the complex numbers. Of major importance in this subject is the extended complex numbers [math]\displaystyle{ \C \cup\{\infty\}, }[/math] the set of complex numbers with a single additional number appended, usually denoted by the infinity symbol [math]\displaystyle{ \infty }[/math] and representing a point at infinity, which is defined to be contained in every exterior domain, making those its topological neighborhoods.

This can intuitively be thought of as wrapping up the infinite edges of the complex plane and pinning them together at the single point [math]\displaystyle{ \infty, }[/math] a one-point compactification, making the extended complex numbers topologically equivalent to a sphere. This equivalence can be extended to a metrical equivalence by mapping each complex number to a point on the sphere via inverse stereographic projection, with the resulting spherical distance applied as a new definition of distance between complex numbers; and in general the geometry of the sphere can be studied using complex arithmetic, and conversely complex arithmetic can be interpreted in terms of spherical geometry. As a consequence, the set of extended complex numbers is often called the Riemann sphere. The set is usually denoted by the symbol for the complex numbers decorated by an asterisk, overline, tilde, or circumflex, for example [math]\displaystyle{ \hat\C = \C \cup\{\infty\}. }[/math]

In the extended complex numbers, for any nonzero complex number [math]\displaystyle{ z, }[/math] ordinary complex arithmetic is extended by the additional rules [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{z}{0}=\infty, }[/math] [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{z}{\infty} = 0, }[/math] [math]\displaystyle{ \infty + 0 = \infty, }[/math] [math]\displaystyle{ \infty + z = \infty, }[/math] [math]\displaystyle{ \infty \cdot z = \infty. }[/math] However, [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{0}{0} }[/math], [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac{\infty}{\infty} }[/math], and [math]\displaystyle{ 0\cdot\infty }[/math] are left undefined.

Higher mathematics

The four basic operations – addition, subtraction, multiplication and division – as applied to whole numbers (positive integers), with some restrictions, in elementary arithmetic are used as a framework to support the extension of the realm of numbers to which they apply. For instance, to make it possible to subtract any whole number from another, the realm of numbers must be expanded to the entire set of integers in order to incorporate the negative integers. Similarly, to support division of any integer by any other, the realm of numbers must expand to the rational numbers. During this gradual expansion of the number system, care is taken to ensure that the "extended operations", when applied to the older numbers, do not produce different results. Loosely speaking, since division by zero has no meaning (is undefined) in the whole number setting, this remains true as the setting expands to the real or even complex numbers.[21]

As the realm of numbers to which these operations can be applied expands there are also changes in how the operations are viewed. For instance, in the realm of integers, subtraction is no longer considered a basic operation since it can be replaced by addition of signed numbers.[22] Similarly, when the realm of numbers expands to include the rational numbers, division is replaced by multiplication by certain rational numbers. In keeping with this change of viewpoint, the question, "Why can't we divide by zero?", becomes "Why can't a rational number have a zero denominator?". Answering this revised question precisely requires close examination of the definition of rational numbers.

In the modern approach to constructing the field of real numbers, the rational numbers appear as an intermediate step in the development that is founded on set theory. First, the natural numbers (including zero) are established on an axiomatic basis such as Peano's axiom system and then this is expanded to the ring of integers. The next step is to define the rational numbers keeping in mind that this must be done using only the sets and operations that have already been established, namely, addition, multiplication and the integers. Starting with the set of ordered pairs of integers, {(a, b)} with b ≠ 0, define a binary relation on this set by (a, b) ≃ (c, d) if and only if ad = bc. This relation is shown to be an equivalence relation and its equivalence classes are then defined to be the rational numbers. It is in the formal proof that this relation is an equivalence relation that the requirement that the second coordinate is not zero is needed (for verifying transitivity).[23][24][25]

Although division by zero cannot be sensibly defined with real numbers and integers, it is possible to consistently define it, or similar operations, in other mathematical structures.

Non-standard analysis

In the hyperreal numbers, division by zero is still impossible, but division by non-zero infinitesimals is possible.[26] The same holds true in the surreal numbers.[27]

Distribution theory

In distribution theory one can extend the function [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{1}{x} }[/math] to a distribution on the whole space of real numbers (in effect by using Cauchy principal values). It does not, however, make sense to ask for a "value" of this distribution at x = 0; a sophisticated answer refers to the singular support of the distribution.

Linear algebra

In matrix algebra, square or rectangular blocks of numbers are manipulated as though they were numbers themselves: matrices can be added and multiplied, and in some cases, a version of division also exists. Dividing by a matrix means, more precisely, multiplying by its inverse. Not all matrices have inverses.[28] For example, a matrix containing only zeros is not invertible.

One can define a pseudo-division, by setting a/b = ab+, in which b+ represents the pseudoinverse of b. It can be proven that if b−1 exists, then b+ = b−1. If b equals 0, then b+ = 0.

Abstract algebra

In abstract algebra, the integers, the rational numbers, the real numbers, and the complex numbers can be abstracted to more general algebraic structures, such as a commutative ring, which is a mathematical structure where addition, subtraction, and multiplication behave as they do in the more familiar number systems, but division may not be defined. Adjoining a multiplicative inverses to a commutative ring is called localization. However, the localization of every commutative ring at zero is the trivial ring, where [math]\displaystyle{ 0 = 1 }[/math], so nontrivial commutative rings do not have inverses at zero, and thus division by zero is undefined for nontrivial commutative rings.

Nevertheless, any number system that forms a commutative ring can be extended to a structure called a wheel in which division by zero is always possible. However, the resulting mathematical structure is no longer a commutative ring, as multiplication no longer distributes over addition. Furthermore, in a wheel, division of an element by itself no longer results in the multiplicative identity element [math]\displaystyle{ 1 }[/math], and if the original system was an integral domain, the multiplication in the wheel no longer results in a cancellative semigroup.

The concepts applied to standard arithmetic are similar to those in more general algebraic structures, such as rings and fields. In a field, every nonzero element is invertible under multiplication; as above, division poses problems only when attempting to divide by zero. This is likewise true in a skew field (which for this reason is called a division ring). However, in other rings, division by nonzero elements may also pose problems. For example, the ring Z/6Z of integers mod 6. The meaning of the expression [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{2}{2} }[/math] should be the solution x of the equation [math]\displaystyle{ 2x = 2 }[/math]. But in the ring Z/6Z, 2 is a zero divisor. This equation has two distinct solutions, x = 1 and x = 4, so the expression [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{2}{2} }[/math] is undefined.

In field theory, the expression [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{a}{b} }[/math] is only shorthand for the formal expression ab−1, where b−1 is the multiplicative inverse of b. Since the field axioms only guarantee the existence of such inverses for nonzero elements, this expression has no meaning when b is zero. Modern texts, that define fields as a special type of ring, include the axiom 0 ≠ 1 for fields (or its equivalent) so that the zero ring is excluded from being a field. In the zero ring, division by zero is possible, which shows that the other field axioms are not sufficient to exclude division by zero in a field.

Computer arithmetic

Floating-point arithmetic

In computing, most numerical calculations are done with floating-point arithmetic, which since the 1980s has been standardized by the IEEE 754 specification. In IEEE floating-point arithmetic, numbers are represented using a sign (positive or negative), a fixed-precision significand and an integer exponent. Numbers whose exponent is too large to represent instead "overflow" to positive or negative infinity (+∞ or −∞), while numbers whose exponent is too small to represent instead "underflow" to positive or negative zero (+0 or −0). A NaN (not a number) value represents undefined results.

In IEEE arithmetic, division of 0/0 or ∞/∞ results in NaN, but otherwise division always produces a well-defined result. Dividing any non-zero number by positive zero (+0) results in an infinity of the same sign as the dividend. Dividing any non-zero number by negative zero (−0) results in an infinity of the opposite sign as the dividend. This definition preserves the sign of the result in case of arithmetic underflow.[29]

For example, using single-precision IEEE arithmetic, if x = −2−149, then x/2 underflows to −0, and dividing 1 by this result produces 1/(x/2) = −∞. The exact result −2150 is too large to represent as a single-precision number, so an infinity of the same sign is used instead to indicate overflow.

Integer arithmetic

Handheld calculators, such as this TI-86, typically halt and display an error message after an attempt to divide by zero.

Integer division by zero is usually handled differently from floating point since there is no integer representation for the result. CPUs differ in behavior: for instance x86 processors trigger a hardware exception, while PowerPC processors silently generate an incorrect result for the division and continue. Because of this inconsistency between platforms, the C and C++ programming languages consider the result of dividing by zero undefined behavior.[30] In typical higher-level programming languages, such as Ada, Python,[31] and Java, an exception is raised for attempted division by zero, which can be handled in another part of the program. In Zig attempting to divide by zero crashes the program.[32] Computer programs often check if the denominator is zero using a conditional (if–then–else) before integer division.

The symbolic mathematics languages Maple and SageMath return an error message for 1/0, while Microsoft Math Solver and Mathematica return ComplexInfinity.

Most calculators will either return an error or state that 1/0 is undefined, but some allow division by zero in special cases. Some Texas Instruments and Hewlett-Packard graphing calculators will evaluate (1/0)2 to ∞.

In proof assistants

Many proof assistants, such as Coq and Lean, define 1/0 = 0. This is due to the requirement that all functions are total. Such a definition does not create contradictions, as further manipulations (such as cancelling out) still require that the divisor is non-zero.[33][34]

Historical accidents

  • On September 21, 1997, a division by zero error in the "Remote Data Base Manager" aboard USS Yorktown (CG-48) brought down all the machines on the network, causing the ship's propulsion system to fail.[35][36]

See also

Notes

  1. Perl BigInt documentation, Perl 5 Porters, https://perldoc.perl.org/bigint.html#Sign, retrieved 1 March 2020 
  2. Cheng 2023, pp. 75–83.
  3. Zazkis & Liljedahl 2009, p. 52–53.
  4. Zazkis & Liljedahl 2009, p. 55–56.
  5. Kochenburger, Ralph J.; Turcio, Carolyn J. (1974), Computers in Modern Society, Santa Barbara: Hamilton, https://archive.org/details/computersinmoder00koch/page/147/mode/1up?q=%22don%27t+try+to+divide+by+zero%22, "Some other operations, including division, can also be performed by the desk calculator (but don't try to divide by zero; the calculator never will stop trying to divide until stopped manually)." 
    For a video demonstration, see: (in en) What happens when you divide by zero on a mechanical calculator?, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=s_hbvRTGcUI, retrieved 2024-01-06 
  6. Zazkis & Liljedahl 2009, pp. 53–54, give an example of a king's heirs equally dividing their inheritance of 12 diamonds, and ask what would happen in the case that all of the heirs died before the king's will could be executed.
  7. In China, Taiwan, and Japan, school textbooks typically distinguish between the ratio [math]\displaystyle{ N:D }[/math] and the value of the ratio [math]\displaystyle{ \tfrac ND. }[/math] By contrast in the USA textbooks typically treat them as two notations for the same thing.
    Lo, Jane-Jane; Watanabe, Tad; Cai, Jinfa (2004), "Developing Ratio Concepts: An Asian Perspective", Mathematics Teaching in the Middle School 9 (7): 362–367, doi:10.5951/MTMS.9.7.0362 
  8. Cengiz, Nesrin; Rathouz, Margaret (2018), "Making Sense of Equivalent Ratios", Mathematics Teaching in the Middle School 24 (3): 148–155, doi:10.5951/mathteacmiddscho.24.3.0148 
  9. Clark, Matthew R.; Berenson, Sarah B.; Cavey, Laurie O. (2003), "A comparison of ratios and fractions and their roles as tools in proportional reasoning", The Journal of Mathematical Behavior 22 (3): 297–317, doi:10.1016/S0732-3123(03)00023-3 
  10. Cheng, Ivan (2010), "Fractions: A New Slant on Slope", Mathematics Teaching in the Middle School 16 (1): 34–41, doi:10.5951/MTMS.16.1.0034 
  11. Cavey, Laurie O.; Mahavier, W. Ted (2010), "Seeing the potential in students' questions", The Mathematics Teacher 104 (2): 133–137, doi:10.5951/MT.104.2.0133 
  12. Wegman, Edward J.; Said, Yasmin H. (2010), "Natural homogeneous coordinates", Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Computational Statistics 2 (6): 678–685, doi:10.1002/wics.122 
  13. Cheng 2023, p. 78; Zazkis & Liljedahl 2009, p. 55
  14. Zazkis & Liljedahl 2009, p. 55.
  15. Cheng 2023, pp. 82–83.
  16. Bunch 1982, p. 14
  17. 17.0 17.1 17.2 Kaplan, Robert (1999), The Nothing That Is: A Natural History of Zero, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 68–75, ISBN 978-0-19-514237-2, https://archive.org/details/nothingthatisnat00kapl 
  18. Bunch 1982, p. 15
  19. "Absurdities due to division by zero: An historical note", The Mathematics Teacher 22 (6): 366–368, 1929, doi:10.5951/MT.22.6.0366 .
  20. Herman, Edwin et al. (2023), "2.2 The Limit of a Function", Calculus, 1, Houston: OpenStax, p. 454, ISBN 978-1-947172-13-5, OCLC 1022848630, https://openstax.org/books/calculus-volume-1/pages/2-2-the-limit-of-a-function 
  21. Klein 1925, p. 63
  22. Klein 1925, p. 26
  23. Schumacher 1996, p. 149
  24. Hamilton 1982, p. 19
  25. Henkin et al. 2012, p. 292
  26. Keisler, H. Jerome (2023), Elementary Calculus: An Infinitesimal Approach, Prindle, Weber & Schmidt, pp. 29–30, https://people.math.wisc.edu/~hkeisler/calc.html 
  27. Conway, John H. (2000-12-11) (in en), On Numbers and Games (2 ed.), CRC Press, p. 20, ISBN 9781568811277, https://books.google.com/books?id=tXiVo8qA5PQC 
  28. Gbur, Greg (2011), Mathematical Methods for Optical Physics and Engineering, Cambridge University Press, pp. 88–93, ISBN 978-0-521-51610-5, Bibcode2011mmop.book.....G 
  29. Cody, W. J. (March 1981), "Analysis of Proposals for the Floating-Point Standard", Computer 14 (3): 65, doi:10.1109/C-M.1981.220379, "With appropriate care to be certain that the algebraic signs are not determined by rounding error, the affine mode preserves order relations while fixing up overflow. Thus, for example, the reciprocal of a negative number which underflows is still negative." 
  30. Wang, Xi; Chen, Haogang; Cheung, Alvin; Jia, Zhihao; Zeldovich, Nickolai; Kaashoek, M. Frans. "APSYS '12: Proceedings of the Asia-Pacific Workshop on Systems". APSYS '12, Seoul, 23–24 July 2012. New York: Association for Computing Machinery. doi:10.1145/2349896.2349905. ISBN 978-1-4503-1669-9. 
  31. "Built-in Exceptions", Python 3 Library Reference, Python Software Foundation, § "Concrete exceptions – exception ZeroDivisionError", https://docs.python.org/3/library/exceptions.html#ZeroDivisionError, retrieved 2024-01-22 
  32. Zig Language Reference, Zig Software Foundation, §41.8 "Division by Zero", https://ziglang.org/documentation/master/#Division-by-Zero, retrieved 2024-01-22 
  33. Tanter, Éric; Tabareau, Nicolas (2015). "Gradual certified programming in coq". Association for Computing Machinery. doi:10.1145/2816707.2816710. "The standard division function on natural numbers in Coq, div, is total and pure, but incorrect: when the divisor is 0, the result is 0." 
  34. Buzzard, Kevin (5 July 2020), Division by zero in type theory: a FAQ, https://xenaproject.wordpress.com/2020/07/05/division-by-zero-in-type-theory-a-faq/, retrieved 2024-01-21 
  35. "Sunk by Windows NT", Wired News, 1998-07-24, https://www.wired.com/1998/07/sunk-by-windows-nt/ 
  36. William Kahan (14 October 2011), Desperately Needed Remedies for the Undebuggability of Large Floating-Point Computations in Science and Engineering, http://www.cs.berkeley.edu/~wkahan/Boulder.pdf 

Sources

Further reading