Choice function

From HandWiki
Short description: Mathematical function


A choice function (selector, selection) is a mathematical function f that is defined on some collection X of nonempty sets and assigns some element of each set S in that collection to S by f(S); f(S) maps S to some element of S. In other words, f is a choice function for X if and only if it belongs to the direct product of X.

An example

Let X = { {1,4,7}, {9}, {2,7} }. Then the function f defined by f({1, 4, 7}) = 7, f({9}) = 9 and f({2, 7}) = 7 is a choice function on X.

History and importance

Ernst Zermelo (1904) introduced choice functions as well as the axiom of choice (AC) and proved the well-ordering theorem,[1] which states that every set can be well-ordered. AC states that every set of nonempty sets has a choice function. A weaker form of AC, the axiom of countable choice (ACω) states that every countable set of nonempty sets has a choice function. However, in the absence of either AC or ACω, some sets can still be shown to have a choice function.

  • If [math]\displaystyle{ X }[/math] is a finite set of nonempty sets, then one can construct a choice function for [math]\displaystyle{ X }[/math] by picking one element from each member of [math]\displaystyle{ X. }[/math] This requires only finitely many choices, so neither AC or ACω is needed.
  • If every member of [math]\displaystyle{ X }[/math] is a nonempty set, and the union [math]\displaystyle{ \bigcup X }[/math] is well-ordered, then one may choose the least element of each member of [math]\displaystyle{ X }[/math]. In this case, it was possible to simultaneously well-order every member of [math]\displaystyle{ X }[/math] by making just one choice of a well-order of the union, so neither AC nor ACω was needed. (This example shows that the well-ordering theorem implies AC. The converse is also true, but less trivial.)

Choice function of a multivalued map

Given two sets X and Y, let F be a multivalued map from X to Y (equivalently, [math]\displaystyle{ F:X\rightarrow\mathcal{P}(Y) }[/math] is a function from X to the power set of Y).

A function [math]\displaystyle{ f: X \rightarrow Y }[/math] is said to be a selection of F, if:

[math]\displaystyle{ \forall x \in X \, ( f(x) \in F(x) ) \,. }[/math]

The existence of more regular choice functions, namely continuous or measurable selections is important in the theory of differential inclusions, optimal control, and mathematical economics.[2] See Selection theorem.

Bourbaki tau function

Nicolas Bourbaki used epsilon calculus for their foundations that had a [math]\displaystyle{ \tau }[/math] symbol that could be interpreted as choosing an object (if one existed) that satisfies a given proposition. So if [math]\displaystyle{ P(x) }[/math] is a predicate, then [math]\displaystyle{ \tau_{x}(P) }[/math] is one particular object that satisfies [math]\displaystyle{ P }[/math] (if one exists, otherwise it returns an arbitrary object). Hence we may obtain quantifiers from the choice function, for example [math]\displaystyle{ P( \tau_{x}(P)) }[/math] was equivalent to [math]\displaystyle{ (\exists x)(P(x)) }[/math].[3]

However, Bourbaki's choice operator is stronger than usual: it's a global choice operator. That is, it implies the axiom of global choice.[4] Hilbert realized this when introducing epsilon calculus.[5]

See also

Notes

  1. Zermelo, Ernst (1904). "Beweis, dass jede Menge wohlgeordnet werden kann". Mathematische Annalen 59 (4): 514–16. doi:10.1007/BF01445300. http://gdz.sub.uni-goettingen.de/no_cache/en/dms/load/img/?IDDOC=28526. 
  2. Border, Kim C. (1989). Fixed Point Theorems with Applications to Economics and Game Theory. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-26564-9. 
  3. Bourbaki, Nicolas. Elements of Mathematics: Theory of Sets. ISBN 0-201-00634-0. 
  4. John Harrison, "The Bourbaki View" eprint.
  5. "Here, moreover, we come upon a very remarkable circumstance, namely, that all of these transfinite axioms are derivable from a single axiom, one that also contains the core of one of the most attacked axioms in the literature of mathematics, namely, the axiom of choice: [math]\displaystyle{ A(a)\to A(\varepsilon(A)) }[/math], where [math]\displaystyle{ \varepsilon }[/math] is the transfinite logical choice function." Hilbert (1925), “On the Infinite”, excerpted in Jean van Heijenoort, From Frege to Gödel, p. 382. From nCatLab.

References