Physics:Measurement problem

From HandWiki
Short description: Theoretical problem in quantum physics

In quantum mechanics, the measurement problem is the problem of how, or whether, wave function collapse occurs. The inability to observe such a collapse directly has given rise to different interpretations of quantum mechanics and poses a key set of questions that each interpretation must answer.

The wave function in quantum mechanics evolves deterministically according to the Schrödinger equation as a linear superposition of different states. However, actual measurements always find the physical system in a definite state. Any future evolution of the wave function is based on the state the system was discovered to be in when the measurement was made, meaning that the measurement "did something" to the system that is not obviously a consequence of Schrödinger evolution. The measurement problem is describing what that "something" is, how a superposition of many possible values becomes a single measured value.

To express matters differently (paraphrasing Steven Weinberg),[1][2] the Schrödinger equation determines the wave function at any later time. If observers and their measuring apparatus are themselves described by a deterministic wave function, why can we not predict precise results for measurements, but only probabilities? As a general question: How can one establish a correspondence between quantum reality and classical reality?[3]

Schrödinger's cat

A thought experiment often used to illustrate the measurement problem is the "paradox" of Schrödinger's cat. A mechanism is arranged to kill a cat if a quantum event, such as the decay of a radioactive atom, occurs. Thus the fate of a large-scale object, the cat, is entangled with the fate of a quantum object, the atom. Prior to observation, according to the Schrödinger equation and numerous particle experiments, the atom is in a quantum superposition, a linear combination of decayed and undecayed states, which evolve with time. Therefore, the cat should also be in a superposition, a linear combination of states that can be characterized as an "alive cat" and states that can be characterized as a "dead cat". Each of these possibilities is associated with a specific nonzero probability amplitude. However, a single, particular observation of the cat does not find a superposition: it always finds either a living cat, or a dead cat. After the measurement the cat is definitively alive or dead. The question is: How are the probabilities converted into an actual, well-defined classical outcome?

Interpretations

Main page: Physics:Interpretations of quantum mechanics

The views often grouped together as the Copenhagen interpretation are the oldest and, collectively, probably still the most widely held attitude about quantum mechanics.[4][5] N. David Mermin coined the phrase "Shut up and calculate!" to summarize Copenhagen-type views, a saying often misattributed to Richard Feynman and which Mermin later found insufficiently nuanced.[6][7]

Generally, views in the Copenhagen tradition posit something in the act of observation which results in the collapse of the wave function. This concept, though often attributed to Niels Bohr, was due to Werner Heisenberg, whose later writings obscured many disagreements he and Bohr had had during their collaboration and that the two never resolved.[8][9] In these schools of thought, wave functions may be regarded as statistical information about a quantum system, and wave function collapse is the updating of that information in response to new data.[10][11] Exactly how to understand this process remains a topic of dispute.[12]

Bohr offered an interpretation that is independent of a subjective observer, or measurement, or collapse; instead, an "irreversible" or effectively irreversible process causes the decay of quantum coherence which imparts the classical behavior of "observation" or "measurement".[13][14][15][16]

Hugh Everett's many-worlds interpretation attempts to solve the problem by suggesting that there is only one wave function, the superposition of the entire universe, and it never collapses—so there is no measurement problem. Instead, the act of measurement is simply an interaction between quantum entities, e.g. observer, measuring instrument, electron/positron etc., which entangle to form a single larger entity, for instance living cat/happy scientist. Everett also attempted to demonstrate how the probabilistic nature of quantum mechanics would appear in measurements, a work later extended by Bryce DeWitt. However, proponents of the Everettian program have not yet reached a consensus regarding the correct way to justify the use of the Born rule to calculate probabilities.[17][18]

The de Broglie–Bohm theory tries to solve the measurement problem very differently: the information describing the system contains not only the wave function, but also supplementary data (a trajectory) giving the position of the particle(s). The role of the wave function is to generate the velocity field for the particles. These velocities are such that the probability distribution for the particle remains consistent with the predictions of the orthodox quantum mechanics. According to de Broglie–Bohm theory, interaction with the environment during a measurement procedure separates the wave packets in configuration space, which is where apparent wave function collapse comes from, even though there is no actual collapse.[19]

A fourth approach is given by objective-collapse models. In such models, the Schrödinger equation is modified and obtains nonlinear terms. These nonlinear modifications are of stochastic nature and lead to a behaviour that for microscopic quantum objects, e.g. electrons or atoms, is unmeasurably close to that given by the usual Schrödinger equation. For macroscopic objects, however, the nonlinear modification becomes important and induces the collapse of the wave function. Objective-collapse models are effective theories. The stochastic modification is thought to stem from some external non-quantum field, but the nature of this field is unknown. One possible candidate is the gravitational interaction as in the models of Diósi and Penrose. The main difference of objective-collapse models compared to the other approaches is that they make falsifiable predictions that differ from standard quantum mechanics. Experiments are already getting close to the parameter regime where these predictions can be tested.[20] The Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber (GRW) theory proposes that wave function collapse happens spontaneously as part of the dynamics. Particles have a non-zero probability of undergoing a "hit", or spontaneous collapse of the wave function, on the order of once every hundred million years.[21] Though collapse is extremely rare, the sheer number of particles in a measurement system means that the probability of a collapse occurring somewhere in the system is high. Since the entire measurement system is entangled (by quantum entanglement), the collapse of a single particle initiates the collapse of the entire measurement apparatus. Because the GRW theory makes different predictions from orthodox quantum mechanics in some conditions, it is not an interpretation of quantum mechanics in a strict sense.

The role of decoherence

Erich Joos and Heinz-Dieter Zeh claim that the phenomenon of quantum decoherence, which was put on firm ground in the 1980s, resolves the problem.[22] The idea is that the environment causes the classical appearance of macroscopic objects. Zeh further claims that decoherence makes it possible to identify the fuzzy boundary between the quantum microworld and the world where the classical intuition is applicable.[23][24] Quantum decoherence becomes an important part of some modern updates of the Copenhagen interpretation based on consistent histories.[25][26] Quantum decoherence does not describe the actual collapse of the wave function, but it explains the conversion of the quantum probabilities (that exhibit interference effects) to the ordinary classical probabilities. See, for example, Zurek,[3] Zeh[23] and Schlosshauer.[27]

The present situation is slowly clarifying, described in a 2006 article by Schlosshauer as follows:[28]

Several decoherence-unrelated proposals have been put forward in the past to elucidate the meaning of probabilities and arrive at the Born rule ... It is fair to say that no decisive conclusion appears to have been reached as to the success of these derivations. ...

As it is well known, [many papers by Bohr insist upon] the fundamental role of classical concepts. The experimental evidence for superpositions of macroscopically distinct states on increasingly large length scales counters such a dictum. Superpositions appear to be novel and individually existing states, often without any classical counterparts. Only the physical interactions between systems then determine a particular decomposition into classical states from the view of each particular system. Thus classical concepts are to be understood as locally emergent in a relative-state sense and should no longer claim a fundamental role in the physical theory.

See also

For a more technical treatment of the mathematics involved in the topic, see Measurement in quantum mechanics.


References and notes

  1. Weinberg, Steven (1998). "The Great Reduction: Physics in the Twentieth Century". The Oxford History of the Twentieth Century. Oxford University Press. p. 26. ISBN 0-19-820428-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=WGvbAApi2roC&pg=PA22. 
  2. Weinberg, Steven (November 2005). "Einstein's Mistakes". Physics Today 58 (11): 31–35. doi:10.1063/1.2155755. Bibcode2005PhT....58k..31W. 
  3. 3.0 3.1 Zurek, Wojciech Hubert (22 May 2003). "Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical". Reviews of Modern Physics 75 (3): 715–775. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.75.715. Bibcode2003RvMP...75..715Z. 
  4. Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Kofler, Johannes; Zeilinger, Anton (August 2013). "A snapshot of foundational attitudes toward quantum mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B 44 (3): 222–230. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004. Bibcode2013SHPMP..44..222S. 
  5. Ball, Philip (2013). "Experts still split about what quantum theory means". Nature. doi:10.1038/nature.2013.12198. https://www.nature.com/news/experts-still-split-about-what-quantum-theory-means-1.12198. 
  6. Mermin, N. David (1989). "What's Wrong with this Pillow?". Physics Today 42 (4): 9. doi:10.1063/1.2810963. Bibcode1989PhT....42d...9D. 
  7. Mermin, N. David (2004). "Could Feynman have said this?". Physics Today 57 (5): 10–11. doi:10.1063/1.1768652. Bibcode2004PhT....57e..10M. 
  8. Howard, Don (December 2004). "Who Invented the "Copenhagen Interpretation"? A Study in Mythology" (in en). Philosophy of Science 71 (5): 669–682. doi:10.1086/425941. ISSN 0031-8248. https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/10.1086/425941. 
  9. Camilleri, Kristian (May 2009). "Constructing the Myth of the Copenhagen Interpretation" (in en). Perspectives on Science 17 (1): 26–57. doi:10.1162/posc.2009.17.1.26. ISSN 1063-6145. http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/10.1162/posc.2009.17.1.26. 
  10. Englert, Berthold-Georg (2013-11-22). "On quantum theory" (in en). The European Physical Journal D 67 (11): 238. doi:10.1140/epjd/e2013-40486-5. ISSN 1434-6079. Bibcode2013EPJD...67..238E. 
  11. Peierls, Rudolf (1991). "In defence of "measurement"" (in en). Physics World 4 (1): 19–21. doi:10.1088/2058-7058/4/1/19. ISSN 2058-7058. 
  12. Healey, Richard (2016). "Quantum-Bayesian and Pragmatist Views of Quantum Theory". in Zalta, Edward N.. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/quantum-bayesian/. 
  13. John Bell (1990), "Against 'measurement'", Physics World 3 (8): 33–41, doi:10.1088/2058-7058/3/8/26 
  14. Niels Bohr (1985), Jørgen Kalckar, ed., Niels Bohr: Collected Works, 6: Foundations of Quantum Physics I (1926-1932), pp. 451–454, https://www.nbarchive.dk/publications/bcw/ 
  15. Stig Stenholm (1983), "To fathom space and time", in Pierre Meystre, Quantum Optics, Experimental Gravitation, and Measurement Theory, Plenum Press, pp. 121, "The role of irreversibility in the theory of measurement has been emphasized by many. Only this way can a permanent record be obtained. The fact that separate pointer positions must be of the asymptotic nature usually associated with irreversibility has been utilized in the measurement theory of Daneri, Loinger and Prosperi (1962). It has been accepted as a formal representation of Bohr's ideas by Rosenfeld (1966)." 
  16. Fritz Haake (April 1, 1993), "Classical motion of meter variables in the quantum theory of measurement", Physical Review A 47 (4): 2506–2517, doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.47.2506, PMID 9909217, Bibcode1993PhRvA..47.2506H 
  17. Kent, Adrian (2010). "One world versus many: the inadequacy of Everettian accounts of evolution, probability, and scientific confirmation". Many Worlds?. Oxford University Press. pp. 307–354. ISBN 9780199560561. OCLC 696602007. 
  18. Barrett, Jeffrey (2018). "Everett's Relative-State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics". in Zalta, Edward N.. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-everett/. 
  19. Sheldon, Goldstein (2017). "Bohmian Mechanics". in Zalta, Edward N.. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-bohm/. 
  20. Angelo Bassi; Kinjalk Lochan; Seema Satin; Tejinder P. Singh; Hendrik Ulbricht (2013). "Models of wave-function collapse, underlying theories, and experimental tests". Reviews of Modern Physics 85 (2): 471–527. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.85.471. Bibcode2013RvMP...85..471B. 
  21. Bell, J. S. (2004). "Are there quantum jumps?". Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics: 201–212.
  22. Joos, E.; Zeh, H. D. (June 1985). "The emergence of classical properties through interaction with the environment". Zeitschrift für Physik B 59 (2): 223–243. doi:10.1007/BF01725541. Bibcode1985ZPhyB..59..223J. 
  23. 23.0 23.1 H. D. Zeh (2003). "Chapter 2: Basic Concepts and Their Interpretation". in E. Joos. Decoherence and the Appearance of a Classical World in Quantum Theory (2nd ed.). Springer-Verlag. pp. 7. ISBN 3-540-00390-8. Bibcode2003dacw.conf....7Z. https://books.google.com/books?id=6eTHcxeNxdUC. 
  24. Jaeger, Gregg (September 2014). "What in the (quantum) world is macroscopic?". American Journal of Physics 82 (9): 896–905. doi:10.1119/1.4878358. Bibcode2014AmJPh..82..896J. 
  25. V. P. Belavkin (1994). "Nondemolition principle of quantum measurement theory". Foundations of Physics 24 (5): 685–714. doi:10.1007/BF02054669. Bibcode1994FoPh...24..685B. 
  26. V. P. Belavkin (2001). "Quantum noise, bits and jumps: uncertainties, decoherence, measurements and filtering". Progress in Quantum Electronics 25 (1): 1–53. doi:10.1016/S0079-6727(00)00011-2. Bibcode2001PQE....25....1B. 
  27. Maximilian Schlosshauer (2005). "Decoherence, the measurement problem, and interpretations of quantum mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics 76 (4): 1267–1305. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.76.1267. Bibcode2004RvMP...76.1267S. 
  28. Maximilian Schlosshauer (January 2006). "Experimental motivation and empirical consistency in minimal no-collapse quantum mechanics". Annals of Physics 321 (1): 112–149. doi:10.1016/j.aop.2005.10.004. Bibcode2006AnPhy.321..112S. 

Further reading

de:Quantenmechanische Messung#Das Messproblem