Medicine:Self-disorder

From HandWiki
Short description: Mental state of a reduced perception of self-awareness
Self-disorder
Other namesIpseity disturbance
SpecialtyPsychiatry
CausesSchizophrenia and other schizophrenia spectrum disorders

A self-disorder, also called ipseity disturbance, is a psychological phenomenon of disruption or diminishing of a person's minimal self the fundamental sense that one's experiences are truly one's own. People with self-disorder feel that their internal experiences are actually external; for example, they may experience their own thoughts as coming from outside themselves, whether in the form of true auditory hallucinations or merely as a vague sense that their thoughts do not belong to them.

There is evidence that self-disorder is characteristic of schizophrenia spectrum disorders such as schizophrenia itself as well as schizotypal personality disorder.[1] This is the true across both psychotic and non-psychotic disorders. The presence or absence of self-disorders has been used to distinguish schizophrenia spectrum disorders from other psychotic disorders, bipolar disorder, borderline personality disorder,[2] and autism spectrum disorder.[3] Detecting self-disorders may also be useful for early intervention in psychosis, since they occur in the prodrome of schizophrenia prior to the emergence of psychotic symptoms.[4][5]

The concept resembles the basic symptoms of schizophrenia, but the term itself was introduced in the early 2000s together with the Examination of Anomalous Self-Experience (EASE) scale, which is used to measure the presence and severity of self-disorder.[6] The concept is associated with the theoretical approach to psychology known as phenomenology.[2]

Minimal self

The minimal (or basic) self has been likened to a "flame that enlightens its surroundings and thereby itself."[2] The sense of minimal self refers to the very basic sense of having experiences that are one's own; it has no properties, unlike the extended self, which is composed of properties such as the person's identity, the person's narrative, their likes and dislikes, and other aspects that are the result of reflection on one's self. The minimal self, however, refers to the "mine-ness" or "given-ness" of experience, that the experiences are that of the person having them in that person's stream of consciousness. These experiences that are part of the minimal self are normally "tacit" and implied, requiring no reflection on the part of the person experiencing to know that the experience is theirs. The minimal self cannot be further elaborated and normally one cannot grasp it upon reflection.[2] The minimal self goes hand-in-hand with immersion in the shared social world, such that "[t]he world is always pregiven, ie, tacitly grasped as a self-evident background of all experiencing and meaning." This is the self-world structure.[7]

De Warren gives an example of the minimal self combined with immersion in the shared social world: "When looking at this tree in my backyard, my consciousness is directed toward the tree and not toward my own act of perception. I am, however, aware of myself as perceiving this tree, yet this self-awareness (or self-consciousness) is not itself thematic."[8] The focus is normally on the tree itself, not on the person's own act of seeing the tree: to know that one is seeing the tree does not require an act of reflection.[citation needed]

Disturbance

In the schizophrenia spectrum disorders, the minimal self and the self-world structure are "constantly challenged, unstable, and oscillating," causing anomalous self-experiences known as self-disorders. These involve the person feeling as if they lack an identity, as if they are not really existing, that the sense of their experiences being their own (the "mine-ness" of their experiential world) is failing or diminishing, as if their inner experiences are no longer private, and that they don't really understand the world. These experiences lead to the person engaging in hyper-reflectivity, or abnormally prolonged and intense self-reflection, to attempt to gain a grasp on these experiences, but such intense reflection may further exacerbate the self-disorders. Self-disorders tend to be chronic, becoming incorporated into the person's way of being and affecting "how" they experience the world and not necessarily "what" they experience. This instability of the minimal self may provoke the onset of psychosis.[7][9]

Similar phenomena can occur in other conditions, such as bipolar disorder and depersonalization disorder, but Sass's (2014) review of the literature comparing accounts of self-experience in various mental disorders shows that serious self-other confusion and "severe erosion of minimal self-experience" only occur in schizophrenia;[10] as an example of the latter, Sass cites the autobiographical account of Elyn Saks, who has schizophrenia, of her experience of "disorganization" in which she felt that thoughts, perceptions, sensations, and even the passage of time became incoherent, and that she had no longer "the solid center from which one experiences reality", which occurred when she was 7 or 8 years old.[11] This disturbance tends to fluctuate over time based on emotions and motivation, accounting for the phenomenon of dialipsis in schizophrenia, where neurocognitive performance tends to be inconsistent over time.[10]

The disturbance of the minimal self may manifest in people in various ways, including as a tendency to inspect one's thoughts in order to know what they are thinking, like a person seeing an image, reading a message, or listening closely to someone talking (audible thoughts; or in German: Gedankenlautwerden). In normal thought, the "signifier" (the images or inner speech representing the thought) and the "meaning" are combined into the "expression", so that the person "inhabits" their thinking, or that both the signifier and the meaning implicitly come to mind together; the person does not need to reflect on their thoughts to understand what they are thinking. In people with self-disorder, however, it is frequently the case that many thoughts are experienced as more like external objects that are not implicitly comprehended. The person must turn their focus toward the thoughts to understand their thoughts because of that lack of implicit comprehension, a split of the signifier and the meaning from each other, where the signifier emerges automatically in the field of awareness but the meaning does not. This is an example of the failing "mine-ness" of the experiential field as the minimal self recedes from its own thoughts, which are consigned to an outer space. This is present chronically, both during and outside of psychosis, and may represent a middle point between normal inner speech and auditory hallucinations, as well as normal experience and first-rank symptoms.[12]

They may also experience uncontrolled multiple trains of thought with different themes simultaneously coursing through one's head interfering with concentration (thought pressure) or often feel they must attend to things with their full attention in order to get done what most people can do without giving it much thought (hyper-reflectivity), which can lead to fatigue.[6][2]

Examination of Anomalous Self-Experience (EASE)

The EASE is a semi-structured interview that attempts to capture the extent of the mainly non-psychotic self-disorders experienced by the person. It is divided into 5 broad sections:

  1. Cognition and stream of consciousness, which covers disturbances in the flow of thoughts and experiences, and includes such self-disorders as "thought pressure", an experienced chaos of unrelated thoughts, "loss of thought ipseity", a sense as if the person does not own their thoughts (but not to the level of psychosis), and "spatialization of experience", which is where the person experiences their thoughts as if they occurred within a space.
  2. Self-awareness and presence, which deals with dissociative experiences of the self and world as well as a tendency toward intense reflection, in addition to a declining understanding of how to interact with others and the world called "perplexity" or "lack of natural evidence."
  3. Bodily experiences, which deals with alienating experiences of the body as well as with "mimetic experiences", the sense of a person that if they move, pseudo-movements of other, unrelated objects are experienced
  4. Demarcation/transitivism, which covers specific disturbances in the person's ego boundaries such as the person confusing their own thoughts, ideas, and feelings for that of their interlocutor.
  5. Existential reorientation, which refers to changes in the person's experience of the world that reflect the effect of self-disorders on the person's worldview.

A large number of these items have affinities with the basic symptoms.[6]

The EASE, and pre-EASE studies attempting to assess basic self-disturbance, has been found in studies to discriminate between people on the schizophrenia spectrum, and those with psychotic bipolar disorder or borderline personality disorder. The EASE has been found to have good reliability, meaning that when 2 clinicians do the assessment, they draw roughly the same conclusions.[2] The items on the EASE were compared against the accounted experiences of depersonalization disorder, finding many affinities, but also differences, reflecting namely the failing sense of "mine-ness" of the experiential world and a tendency to confuse the self with the world, others, or both.[13]

EASE items

Domain 1: Stream of consciousness
Domain 2: Self-awareness and presence
Domain 3: Bodily experiences
Domain 4: Transitivism/demarcation
Domain 5: Existential reorientation

Examination of Anomalous World Experience (EAWE)

The EAWE is the companion interview to the EASE that focuses on the person's experiences with the world, rather than with the self. There are 6 domains:

  1. Space and objects, which deals with the person's experience with space and physical objects, with disorders including hallucinations, distortions of spatial relationships, and experiences of seeing the same object in multiple ways at the same time (called "contamination" on the Rorschach test).
  2. Time and events, which deals with the person's experience with time, with disorders involving time speeding up or slowing down, time breaking up or becoming fragmented, and constant anticipation of something major about to happen.
  3. Other persons, which deals with the person's experience of other people, with disorders including disruptions of the sense of ego boundaries with other people, referential ideation based on actions or words by other people, and loss or lack of the ability to naturally understand social situations and social cues leading to attempts to compensate through increased focus or concentration,.
  4. Language, which deals with reduced fluency and disruption of prose in one's native language, distortions in the person's expression which causes others to misunderstand the person, problems with concrete and abstract concepts, and distraction by individual words and phrases leading to the person having difficulty following what they are reading or listening to.
  5. Atmosphere, which deals with the person's overall feeling-state of the world, with disorders including derealization (particularly The Truman Show-style derealization), objects no longer having normal meaning, hyper-awareness of things that normally stay in the background of awareness, apophanous mood, and a sense of radical changes in the very structure of the universe itself.
  6. Existential orientation, which deals with radical changes in a person's worldview, dealing with such things as rejecting society's conventions and rules, being extremely open to believing new ideas, and grandiosity which involves the person considering others to be inferior, like insects compared to them.[15]

EAWE items

Domain 1: Space and objects
Domain 2: Time and events
Domain 3: Other persons
Domain 4: Language
Domain 5: Atmosphere
Domain 6: Existential orientation

*Indicates experience that can also occur in other primary psychotic or mood disorders outside the schizophrenia spectrum, such as delusional disorder, major depressive disorder, or bipolar disorder.

Clinical relevance

The presence of self-disorders may have predictive power for whether those with an at risk mental state will develop psychosis;[16][17] the risk of suicidal ideation and suicide by people with schizophrenia, though depression would also be an important factor;[18] predicting initial social dysfunction in people with either schizophrenic or bipolar psychosis;[19] and whether a person will move to a schizophrenia spectrum diagnosis later.[20]

Considering the presence of self-disorders is useful when attempting to differentially diagnose disorders that can be confused with schizophrenia spectrum disorders. Autism spectrum disorder and schizotypal personality disorder can appear outwardly similar but have different etiologies and require different treatment approaches.[3][21] The presence of self-disorders is evidence for a diagnosis of schizotypal personality disorder over autism spectrum disorder.[21][22] Likewise, in the case of first instance psychosis, self-disorders are indicative of a diagnosis of schizophrenia in favor of other psychotic disorders.[23]

The presence of self-disorders may cause reduced person insight into their illness through the alteration of the basic structures of consciousness.[2][7]

Self-disorders are difficult for the people experiencing them to articulate spontaneously;[6][24] and are not well-known, by either the general public or professionals in the field. Because of this, people will often make vague, clichéd complaints that mimic the symptoms of other mental disorders, symptoms such as "fatigue" or "concentration difficulties". Were a knowledgeable clinician to probe deeper, however, the underlying self-disorders may be assessed and help clarify the nature of the person's illness. In their review, Parnas, et al. (2014) say, "The psychiatrist's acquaintance with the phenomenon of 'non-specific specificity' is, in our view, extremely important in the context of early diagnostic assessment, especially of people presenting with a vague, unelaborated picture of maladjustment, underperformance, chronic malaise and dysphoria, negative symptoms, or hypochondriac preoccupations." People with schizophrenia often describe their self-disorders as causing more suffering for them than psychosis.[2]

Self-disorders underlie most of the first-rank symptoms, those often termed passivity phenomena. There is a current proposal to list self-disorder as one of the symptoms of schizophrenia in the upcoming ICD-11.[25]

Evidence

The first systematic review of empirical studies on self-disorders based on the EASE scale was published in 2021. It found consistent support for the concept as a characteristic component of schizophrenia spectrum disorders and not other mental disorders.[1] Another systematic review and meta-analysis from 2022 covering an aggregated sample of 810 patients found good evidence to support the existence of self-disorders as core clinical feature in schizophrenia spectrum disorders.[26] The concept and its link to schizophrenia was likewise supported by a 2021 meta-analysis.[27]

Future directions and controversy

In a 2014 review, Postmes, et al., suggested that self-disorders and psychosis may arise from attempts to compensate for perceptual incoherence and proposed a hypothesis for how the interaction among these phenomena and the person's attempts to resolve the incoherence give rise to schizophrenia. The problems with the integration of sensory information create problems for the person in keeping a grip on the world, and since the self-world interaction is fundamentally linked to the basic sense of self, the latter is also disrupted as a result.[28] Sass and Borda have studied the correlates of the dimensions of self-disorders, namely disturbed grip (perplexity, difficulty "getting" stuff most people can get), hyperreflexivity (where thoughts, feelings, sensations, and objects pop up uncontrollably in the field of awareness, as well dysfunctional reflecting on matters and the self), and diminished self-affection (where the person has difficulty being "affected" by aspects of the self, experiencing those aspects as if they existed in an outer space), and have proposed how both primary and secondary factors may arise from dysfunctions in perceptual organization and multisensory integration.[29][30]

In a 2013 review, Mishara, et al., criticized the concept of the minimal self as an explanation for self-disorder, saying that it is unfalsifiable, and that self-disorder arises primarily from difficulty integrating different aspects of the self as well as having difficulty distinguishing self and other, as proposed by Lysaker and Lysaker: Ichstörung or ego disorder, as they say, in schizophrenia arises from disturbed relationships not from the "solipsistic" concept of the self as proposed by Sass, Parnas, and others.[31] In his review, Sass agrees that the focus of research into self-disorder has focused too much on the self, and mentions attempts to look at disturbances in the person's relationship with other people and the world, with work being done to create an Examination of Anomalous World Experience, which will look at the person's anomalous experiences regarding time, space, persons, language, and atmosphere; he suggests there are problems with both the self and the world in people with self-disorder, and that it may be better conceptualized as a "presence-disturbance".[10] Parnas acknowledges the Lysaker model, but says that it is not incompatible with the concept of the minimal self, as they deal with different levels of self-hood.[2]

History

The concept of a basic self-disturbance in schizophrenia appears in all the foundational texts on the disease.[2][32] The basic symptoms of schizophrenia include descriptions of self-disorders.[6] Likewise, Kurt Schneider's first-rank symptoms, especially his concept of ego disturbances [de] as well as the so-called passivity phenomena may be considered as examples of self-disorders.[33][34] Similar concepts were also discussed by Karl Jaspers.[34] The concept of "ontological insecurity", which resembles self-disorder, was proposed by R. D. Laing in 1960.[35]

The publication of the DSM-III (1980) lead to an increased emphasis on concrete signs and symptoms of mental disorders over the subjective experiences underlying those symptoms; in other words, it privileged a behaviorist approach to diagnosis. Because the concept of self-disorders had been difficult to operationalize, it began to be criticized as overly vague and too subjective; indeed, little systematic or empirical research was done on the concept in the 20th century. It therefore began to fall out of clinical use and soon disappeared entirely from training programs in the United States.[2][32][36]

A notable exception to this trend was the Bonn Scale for the Assessment of Basic Symptoms (BSABS), created in the 1980s to assess sub-clinical affective, cognitive and perceptual disturbances, as well as basic self-disturbance.[36] In many studies, basic symptoms as measured by the BSABS were found to aggregate in people with schizophrenic and schizotypal disorders.[24]

In early 2000s, a group of researchers including Danish psychiatrist Josef Parnas sought to operationalize and revive the idea of schizophrenia as a disorder of the minimal self.[34] This work resulted in the creation of the EASE, which was published in 2005.[6][2] The scale was based on phenomenological interviews with first-admission people with schizophrenia spectrum disorders, to enable empirical research of self-disorders.[6][2] It was also partially based on the BSABS, but more focused on items relating specifically to disturbed self-experience.[34] The creation of the EASE resulted in an uptick in research into the topic, and the first systematic review of the concept was published in The Lancet Psychiatry in 2021, finding good empirical support for self-disorders as a defining characteristic of schizophrenia spectrum disorders.[1]

See also

References

  1. 1.0 1.1 1.2 Henriksen, Mads Gram; Raballo, Andrea; Nordgaard, Julie (2021-11-08). "Self-disorders and psychopathology: a systematic review" (in en). The Lancet Psychiatry 8 (11): 1001–1012. doi:10.1016/S2215-0366(21)00097-3. PMID 34688345. https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S2215036621000973. 
  2. 2.00 2.01 2.02 2.03 2.04 2.05 2.06 2.07 2.08 2.09 2.10 2.11 2.12 Josef Parnas & Mads Gram Henriksen (September 2014). "Disordered self in the schizophrenia spectrum: a clinical and research perspective". Harvard Review of Psychiatry 22 (5): 251–265. doi:10.1097/HRP.0000000000000040. PMID 25126763. 
  3. 3.0 3.1 Nilsson, Maria; Handest, Peter; Nylander, Lena; Pedersen, Lennart; Carlsson, Jessica; Arnfred, Sidse (2019). "Arguments for a Phenomenologically Informed Clinical Approach to Autism Spectrum Disorder" (in en). Psychopathology 52 (3): 153–160. doi:10.1159/000500294. ISSN 0254-4962. PMID 31170725. https://www.karger.com/Article/FullText/500294. 
  4. Valle, Rubén; Perales, Alberto (October 2019). "Self-disorders in early stages of the schizophrenia spectrum" (in en). Revista Colombiana de Psiquiatría (English Edition) 48 (4): 244–251. doi:10.1016/j.rcpeng.2018.02.004. https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S2530312019300463. 
  5. Parnas, Josef; Raballo, Andrea; Handest, Peter; Jansson, Lennart; Vollmer-Larsen, Anne; Saebye, Ditte (October 2011). "Self-experience in the early phases of schizophrenia: 5-year follow-up of the Copenhagen Prodromal Study" (in en). World Psychiatry 10 (3): 200–204. doi:10.1002/j.2051-5545.2011.tb00057.x. PMID 21991279. PMC 3188774. https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/j.2051-5545.2011.tb00057.x. 
  6. 6.0 6.1 6.2 6.3 6.4 6.5 6.6 Parnas, Josef; Moller, Paul; Kircher, Tilo; Thalbitzer, Jorgen; Jansson, Lennart; Handest, Peter; Zahavi, Dan (September 2005). "EASE: Examination of Anomalous Self-Experience". Psychopathology 38 (5): 236–258. doi:10.1159/000088441. PMID 16179811. https://vestreviken.no/Documents/Helsefaglig/Selvforstyrrelser/Original%20avhandling%20om%20EASE%20-%20Engelsk.pdf. 
  7. 7.0 7.1 7.2 Mads G. Henriksen & Josef Parnas (May 2014). "Self-disorders and schizophrenia: a phenomenological reappraisal of poor insight and noncompliance". Schizophrenia Bulletin 40 (3): 542–547. doi:10.1093/schbul/sbt087. PMID 23798710. 
  8. De Warren, N.. Husserl and the Promise of Time. New York: Cambridge University Press. , cited in Brice Martin, Marc Wittmann, Nicolas Franck, Michel Cermolacce, Fabrice Berna & Anne Giersch (2014). "Temporal structure of consciousness and minimal self in schizophrenia". Frontiers in Psychology 5: 1175. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01175. PMID 25400597. 
  9. Louis A. Sass & Josef Parnas (2003). "Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self". Schizophrenia Bulletin 29 (3): 427–444. doi:10.1093/oxfordjournals.schbul.a007017. PMID 14609238. 
  10. 10.0 10.1 10.2 Sass, Louis A. (2014). "Self-disturbance and schizophrenia: Structure, specificity, pathogenesis (Current issues, New directions)". Schizophrenia Research 152 (1): 5–11. doi:10.1016/j.schres.2013.05.017. ISSN 1573-2509. PMID 23773296. 
  11. Saks, Elyn (2007). The center cannot hold : my journey through madness. New York: Hyperion. ISBN 978-1-4013-0944-2. https://archive.org/details/centercannothold00saks_0. 
  12. Kendler, K.S.; Parnas, J. (2012). Philosophical Issues in Psychiatry II: Nosology. International Perspectives in Philosophy & Psychiatry. OUP Oxford. pp. 242–243. ISBN 978-0-19-964220-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=p3qOet7tpJsC&pg=PA242. Retrieved 2016-04-12. 
  13. Louis Sass, Elizabeth Pienkos, Barnaby Nelson & Nick Medford (June 2013). "Anomalous self-experience in depersonalization and schizophrenia: a comparative investigation". Consciousness and Cognition 22 (2): 430–441. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2013.01.009. PMID 23454432. 
  14. Rasmussen, A. Rosen; Parnas, Josef (2015). "Pathologies of imagination in schizophrenia spectrum disorders". Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica 131 (3): 157–161. doi:10.1111/acps.12323. PMID 25098736. 
  15. Sass, Louis; Pienkos, Elizabeth; Skodlar, Borut; Stanghellini, Giovanni; Fuchs, Thomas; Parnas, Josef; Jones, Nev (2017-01-01). "EAWE: Examination of Anomalous World Experience". Psychopathology 50 (1): 10–54. doi:10.1159/000454928. ISSN 1423-033X. PMID 28268224. https://www.researchgate.net/profile/Thomas-Fuchs-6/publication/314288757_EAWE_Examination_of_Anomalous_World_Experience/links/59de7c56aca27247d7943b45/EAWE-Examination-of-Anomalous-World-Experience.pdf. 
  16. Andrea Raballo, Elena Pappagallo, Alice Dell' Erba, Nella Lo Cascio, Martina Patane', Eva Gebhardt, Tommaso Boldrini, Laura Terzariol, Massimiliano Angelone, Alberto Trisolini, Paolo Girardi & Paolo Fiori Nastro (January 2016). "Self-Disorders and Clinical High Risk for Psychosis: An Empirical Study in Help-Seeking Youth Attending Community Mental Health Facilities". Schizophrenia Bulletin 42 (4): 926–32. doi:10.1093/schbul/sbv223. PMID 26757754. 
  17. Barnaby Nelson, Andrew Thompson & Alison R. Yung (November 2012). "Basic self-disturbance predicts psychosis onset in the ultra high risk for psychosis "prodromal" population". Schizophrenia Bulletin 38 (6): 1277–1287. doi:10.1093/schbul/sbs007. PMID 22349924. 
  18. Elisabeth Haug, Ingrid Melle, Ole A. Andreassen, Andrea Raballo, Unni Bratlien, Merete Oie, Lars Lien & Paul Moller (July 2012). "The association between anomalous self-experience and suicidality in first-episode schizophrenia seems mediated by depression". Comprehensive Psychiatry 53 (5): 456–460. doi:10.1016/j.comppsych.2011.07.005. PMID 21871617. 
  19. Elisabeth Haug, Merete Oie, Ole A. Andreassen, Unni Bratlien, Andrea Raballo, Barnaby Nelson, Paul Moller & Ingrid Melle (April 2014). "Anomalous self-experiences contribute independently to social dysfunction in the early phases of schizophrenia and psychotic bipolar disorder". Comprehensive Psychiatry 55 (3): 475–482. doi:10.1016/j.comppsych.2013.11.010. PMID 24378241. 
  20. Josef Parnas, John Carter & Julie Nordgaard (February 2016). "Premorbid self-disorders and lifetime diagnosis in the schizophrenia spectrum: a prospective high-risk study". Early Intervention in Psychiatry 10 (1): 45–53. doi:10.1111/eip.12140. PMID 24725282. 
  21. 21.0 21.1 Nilsson, Maria; Arnfred, Sidse; Carlsson, Jessica; Nylander, Lena; Pedersen, Lennart; Mortensen, Erik Lykke; Handest, Peter (2020-01-04). "Self-Disorders in Asperger Syndrome Compared to Schizotypal Disorder: A Clinical Study" (in en). Schizophrenia Bulletin 46 (1): 121–129. doi:10.1093/schbul/sbz036. ISSN 0586-7614. PMID 31050761. PMC 6942161. https://academic.oup.com/schizophreniabulletin/article/46/1/121/5485220. 
  22. Parvaiz, Rizwan; Vindbjerg, Erik; Crespi, Bernard; Happe, Francesca; Schalbroeck, Rik; Al-Sayegh, Zainab; Danielsen, Ida-Marie; Tonge, Bruce et al. (2023-03-28). "Protocol for the development and testing of the schiZotypy Autism Questionnaire (ZAQ) in adults: a new screening tool to discriminate autism spectrum disorder from schizotypal disorder". BMC Psychiatry (Springer Science and Business Media LLC) 23 (1): 200. doi:10.1186/s12888-023-04690-3. ISSN 1471-244X. PMID 36978026. 
  23. Spark, Jessica; Gawęda, Łukasz; Allott, Kelly; Hartmann, Jessica A.; Jack, Bradley N.; Koren, Dan; Lavoie, Suzie; Li, Emily et al. (February 2021). "Distinguishing schizophrenia spectrum from non-spectrum disorders among young patients with first episode psychosis and at high clinical risk: The role of basic self-disturbance and neurocognition" (in en). Schizophrenia Research 228: 19–28. doi:10.1016/j.schres.2020.11.061. PMID 33434729. https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S0920996420306526. 
  24. 24.0 24.1 Frauke Schultze-Lutter (January 2009). "Subjective symptoms of schizophrenia in research and the clinic: the basic symptom concept". Schizophrenia Bulletin 35 (1): 5–8. doi:10.1093/schbul/sbn139. PMID 19074497. 
  25. Heinz, A.; Voss, M.; Lawrie, S. M.; Mishara, A.; Bauer, M.; Gallinat, J.; Juckel, G.; Lang, U. et al. (2016-07-15). "Shall we really say goodbye to first rank symptoms?". European Psychiatry 37: 8–13. doi:10.1016/j.eurpsy.2016.04.010. ISSN 1778-3585. PMID 27429167. 
  26. Burgin, Sam; Reniers, Renate; Humpston, Clara (2022-01-21). "Prevalence and assessment of self-disorders in the schizophrenia spectrum: a systematic review and meta-analysis" (in en). Scientific Reports 12 (1): 1165. doi:10.1038/s41598-022-05232-9. ISSN 2045-2322. PMID 35064201. Bibcode2022NatSR..12.1165B. 
  27. Raballo, Andrea; Poletti, Michele; Preti, Antonio; Parnas, Josef (2021-01-22). "The Self in the Spectrum: A Meta-analysis of the Evidence Linking Basic Self-Disorders and Schizophrenia". Schizophrenia Bulletin 47 (4): 1007–1017. doi:10.1093/schbul/sbaa201. PMID 33479736. 
  28. Postmes, L.; Sno, H.N.; Goedhart, S.; van der Stel, J.; Heering, H.D.; de Haan, L. (2014). "Schizophrenia as a self-disorder due to perceptual incoherence". Schizophrenia Research 152 (1): 41–50. doi:10.1016/j.schres.2013.07.027. ISSN 1573-2509. PMID 23973319. 
  29. Borda, Juan P.; Sass, Louis A. (2015). "Phenomenology and neurobiology of self disorder in schizophrenia: Primary factors". Schizophrenia Research 169 (1–3): 464–473. doi:10.1016/j.schres.2015.09.024. ISSN 1573-2509. PMID 26516103. 
  30. Sass, Louis A.; Borda, Juan P. (2015). "Phenomenology and neurobiology of self disorder in schizophrenia: Secondary factors". Schizophrenia Research 169 (1–3): 474–482. doi:10.1016/j.schres.2015.09.025. ISSN 1573-2509. PMID 26603059. 
  31. Mishara, A. L.; Lysaker, P. H.; Schwartz, M. A. (2013). "Self-disturbances in Schizophrenia: History, Phenomenology, and Relevant Findings From Research on Metacognition". Schizophrenia Bulletin 40 (1): 5–12. doi:10.1093/schbul/sbt169. ISSN 0586-7614. PMID 24319117. 
  32. 32.0 32.1 Nancy C. Andreasen (January 2007). "DSM and the death of phenomenology in america: an example of unintended consequences". Schizophrenia Bulletin 33 (1): 108–112. doi:10.1093/schbul/sbl054. PMID 17158191. 
  33. Nordgaard, Julie; Henriksen, Mads Gram; Berge, Jonas; Nilsson, Lars Siersbæk (2019-08-01). "First-rank symptoms and self-disorders in schizophrenia" (in en). Schizophrenia Research 210: 306–307. doi:10.1016/j.schres.2019.06.027. ISSN 0920-9964. https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0920996419302634. 
  34. 34.0 34.1 34.2 34.3 Bürgy, Martin (2011). "Ego Disturbances in the Sense of Kurt Schneider: Historical and Phenomenological Aspects" (in en). Psychopathology 44 (5): 320–328. doi:10.1159/000325059. ISSN 0254-4962. https://www.karger.com/Article/FullText/325059. 
  35. Nour, Matthew M.; Barrera, Alvaro (November 2015). "Schizophrenia, Subjectivity, and Mindreading" (in en). Schizophrenia Bulletin 41 (6): 1214–1219. doi:10.1093/schbul/sbv035. ISSN 0586-7614. PMID 25848120. PMC 4601706. https://academic.oup.com/schizophreniabulletin/article-lookup/doi/10.1093/schbul/sbv035. 
  36. 36.0 36.1 Vollmer-Larsen, Anne; Handest, Peter; Parnas, Josef (2007). "Reliability of Measuring Anomalous Experience: The Bonn Scale for the Assessment of Basic Symptoms" (in en). Psychopathology 40 (5): 345–348. doi:10.1159/000106311. ISSN 0254-4962. https://www.karger.com/Article/FullText/106311. 

External links

Classification
External resources