Philosophy:Existence
Existence is the state of being real or participating in reality. The terms "being", "reality", and "actuality" are often used as close synonyms. Existence contrasts with nonexistence, nothingness, and nonbeing. A common distinction is between the existence of an entity and its essence, which refers to the entity's nature or essential qualities.
The main philosophical discipline studying existence is called ontology. The orthodox view is that it is a second-order property or a property of properties. According to this view, to say that a thing exists means that its properties are instantiated. A different view holds that existence is a first-order property or a property of individuals. This means that existence has the same ontological status as other properties of individuals, like color and shape. Meinongians accept this idea and hold that not all individuals have this property: they state that there are some individuals that do not exist. This view is rejected by universalists, who see existence as a universal property of every individual.
Various types of existence are discussed in the academic literature. Singular existence is the existence of individual entities while general existence refers to the existence of concepts or universals. Other distinctions are between abstract and concrete existence, between possible, contingent, and necessary existence, and between physical and mental existence. A closely related issue is whether different types of entities exist in different ways or to different degrees.
A key question in ontology is whether there is a reason for existence in general or why anything at all exists. The concept of existence is relevant to various fields, including logic, epistemology, philosophy of mind, philosophy of language, and existentialism.
Existence is the state of being real and to exist means to have being or to participate in reality.[1] Existence is what sets real entities apart from imaginary ones[2] and can refer both to individual entities or to the totality of reality.[3] The word "existence" entered the English language in the late 14th century from old French and has its roots in the medieval Latin term ex(s)istere, which means to stand forth, to appear, and to arise.[4] Existence is studied by the subdiscipline of metaphysics known as ontology.[5]
The terms "being", "reality", and "actuality" are closely related to existence.[6] They are usually used as synonyms of "existence" but their meanings as technical terms may come apart.[7] According to metaphysicist Alexius Meinong, for example, all entities have being but not all have existence. He argues that merely possible objects, like Santa Claus, have being but lack existence.[8] Ontologist Takashi Yagisawa contrasts existence with reality. He sees "reality" as the more fundamental term since it characterizes all entities equally and defines existence as a relative term that connects an entity to the world that it inhabits.[9] According to Gottlob Frege, actuality is more narrow than existence since only actual entities can produce and undergo changes, in contrast to non-actual existing entities, like numbers and sets.[10]
Existence contrasts with nonexistence, which refers to a lack of reality. It is controversial whether objects can be divided into existent and nonexistent objects. This distinction is sometimes used to explain how it is possible to think of fictional objects, like dragons and unicorns. But the concept of nonexistent objects is not generally accepted.[11] Closely related contrasting terms are nothingness and nonbeing.[12]
Another contrast is between existence and essence. Essence refers to the intrinsic nature or defining qualities of an entity. The essence of something determines what kind of entity it is and how it differs from other kinds of entities. Essence corresponds to what an entity is while existence corresponds to the fact that it is. For instance, it is possible to understand what an object is and grasp its nature even if one does not know whether this object exists.[13]
Some philosophers, like Edmund Husserl and Quentin Boyce Gibson, hold that existence is an elementary concept, meaning that it cannot be defined in other terms without involving circularity. This would imply that it may be difficult or impossible to characterize existence or to talk about its nature in a non-trivial manner.[14]
A closely related issue concerns the distinction between thin and thick concepts of existence. Thin concepts understand existence as a logical property that every existing thing shares. It does not include any substantial content about the metaphysical implications of having existence. An example of a thin concept of existence is to state that existence is the same as the logical property of self-identity.[15] Thick concepts of existence encompass a metaphysical analysis of what it means that something exists and what essential features existence implies. For example, George Berkeley's claim that esse est percipi presents a thick concept of existence. It can be translated as "to be is to be perceived" and highlights the mental nature of all existence.[16]
Some philosophers emphasize that there is a difference between entities and what fundamentally makes them the entities they are.[17] This distinction was introduced by Martin Heidegger, who calls it the ontological difference and contrasts individual beings with being, the latter of which he presents as the horizon against which beings become the specific beings that they are.[18][lower-alpha 1]
Theories of the nature of existence
Theories of the nature of existence aim to explain what it means for something to exist. The central dispute regarding the nature of existence is whether it should be understood as a property of individuals.[21]
The two main theories of existence are first-order theories and second-order theories. First-order theories understand existence as a property of individuals. Some first-order theories see it as a property of all individuals while others hold that there are some individuals that do not exist. Second-order theories hold that existence is a second-order property, that is, a property of properties.[22]
A central challenge for the different theories of the nature of existence is to understand how it is possible to coherently deny the existence of something, like the claim that "Santa Claus does not exist". One difficulty consists in explaining how the name "Santa Claus" can be meaningful even though there is no Santa Claus.[23]
Second-order theories
Second-order theories are often seen as the orthodox position. They understand existence as a second-order property rather than a first-order property.[24] For instance, the Empire State Building is an individual object and being 443.2 meters tall is a first-order property of it. Being instantiated is a property of being 443.2 meters tall and therefore a second-order property. According to second-order theories, to talk about existence is to talk about which properties have instances.[25] For example, this view states that the sentence "God exists" means that "Godhood is instantiated" rather than "God has the property of existing".[2]
A key motivation of second-order theories is that existence is in important ways different from regular properties like being a building and being 443.2 meters tall: regular properties express what an object is like but existence does not.[26] According to this view, existence is more fundamental than regular properties since, without it, objects cannot instantiate any properties.[27]
Second-order theorists usually hold that quantifiers rather than predicates express existence.[28] Quantifiers are terms that talk about the quantity of objects that have certain properties. Existential quantifiers express that there is at least one object, like the expressions like "some" and "there exists", as in "some cows eat grass" and "there exists an even prime number".[29] In this regard, existence is closely related to counting since to claim that something exists is to claim that the corresponding concept has one or more instances.[25]
Second-order views imply that a sentence like "egg-laying mammals exist" is misleading since the word "exist" is used as a predicate in them. They hold instead that their true logical form is better expressed in reformulations like "there exist entities that are egg-laying mammals". This way, existence has the role of a quantifier while egg-laying mammals is the predicate. Quantifier constructions can also be used to express negative existential statements. For instance, the sentence "talking tigers do not exist" can be expressed as "it is not the case that there exist talking tigers".[30]
Many ontologists accept that second-order theories provide a correct analysis of many types of existential sentences. However, it is controversial whether it is correct for all cases.[31] One difficulty is caused by so-called negative singular existentials, which are statements that deny that a particular object exists, like the sentence "Ronald McDonald does not exist". Singular terms, like Ronald McDonald, seem to refer to individuals, which poses a difficulty since negative singular existentials deny that this individual exists. This makes it unclear how the singular term can refer to the individual in the first place. One influential solution to this problem was proposed by Bertrand Russell. He holds that singular terms do not directly refer to individuals but are instead descriptions of individuals. Positive singular existentials affirm that an object matching the descriptions exists while negative singular existentials deny that an object matching the descriptions exists. According to this view, the sentence "Ronald McDonald does not exist" expresses the idea that "it is not the case that there is a unique happy hamburger clown".[32]
First-order theories
First-order theories claim that existence is a property of individuals. They are less widely accepted than second-order theories but also have some influential proponents. There are two types of first-order theories. According to Meinongianism, existence is a property of some but not all entities, which implies that there are nonexistent entities. According to universalism, existence is a universal property instantiated by every entity.[33]
Meinongianism
Meinongianism is a view about existence defended by Meinong and his followers. Its main claim is that there are some entities that do not exist, meaning that objecthood is independent of existence. Proposed examples of nonexistent objects are merely possible objects, like flying pigs, as well as fictional and mythical objects, like Sherlock Holmes and Zeus. According to this view, these objects are real and have being even though they do not exist.[34] Meinong states that there is an object for any combination of properties. For example, there is an object that only has the single property of being a singer without any additional properties. This means that neither the attribute of wearing a dress nor the absence of it applies to this object. Meinong also includes impossible objects, like round squares.[35]
Meinongians state that sentences describing what Sherlock Holmes and Zeus are like refer to nonexisting objects. They are true or false depending on whether these objects have the properties ascribed to them.[36] For instance, the sentence "Pegasus has wings" is true because having wings is a property of Pegasus, even though Pegasus lacks the property of existing.[37]
One key motivation of Meinongianism is to explain how negative singular existentials, like "Ronald McDonald does not exist", can be true. Meinongians accept the idea that singular terms, like "Ronald McDonald" refer to individuals. For them, a negative singular existential is true if the individual it refers to does not exist.[38]
Meinongianism has important implications for how to understand quantification. According to an influential view defended by Willard Van Orman Quine, the domain of quantification is restricted to existing objects. This view implies that quantifiers carry ontological commitments about what exists and what does not exist. Meinongianism differs from this view by holding that the widest domain of quantification includes both existing and nonexisting objects.[20]
Some aspects of Meinongianism are controversial and have received substantial criticism. According to one objection, one cannot distinguish between being an object and being an existing object.[37] A closely related criticism rests on the idea that objects cannot have properties if they do not exist.[37] A further objection is that Meinongianism leads to an "overpopulated universe" since there is an object corresponding to any combination of properties.[20] A more specific criticism rejects the idea that there are incomplete and impossible objects.[39]
Universalism
Universalists agree with Meinongians that existence is a property of individuals. But they deny that there are nonexistent entities. They state instead that existence is a universal property: all entities have it, meaning that everything exists. One approach is to hold that existence is the same as self-identity. According to the law of identity, every object is identical to itself or has the property of self-identity. This can be expressed in predicate logic as [math]\displaystyle{ \forall x (x = x) }[/math].[40]
An influential argument in favor of universalism rests on the claim that to deny the existence of something is contradictory. This conclusion follows from the premises that one can only deny the existence of something by referring to that entity and that one can only refer to entities that exist.[40]
Universalists have proposed different ways of interpreting negative singular existentials. According to one view, names of fictional entities like "Ronald McDonald" refer to abstract objects. Abstract objects exist even though they do not exist in space and time. This means that, when understood in a strict sense, all negative singular existentials are false, including the claim that "Ronald McDonald does not exist". However, universalists can interpret such sentences slightly differently in relation to the context. In everyday life, for example, people use sentences like "Ronald McDonald does not exist" to express the idea that Ronald McDonald does not exist as a concrete object, which is true.[41] A different approach is to claim that negative singular existentials lack a truth value since their singular terms do not refer to anything. According to this view, they are neither true nor false but meaningless.[42]
Types of existing entities
Different types of existing entities are discussed in the academic literature. Many discussions revolve around the questions of what those types are, whether entities of a specific type exist, how entities of different types are related to each other, and whether some types are more fundamental than others.[43] Examples are questions like whether souls exist, whether there are abstract, fictional, and universal entities, and whether besides the actual world and its objects, there are also possible worlds and objects.[44]
Singular and general
One distinction is between singular and general existence. Singular existence is the existence of individual entities. For example, the sentence "Angela Merkel exists" expresses the existence of one particular person. General existence pertains to general concepts, properties, or universals. For instance, the sentence "politicians exist" states that the general term "politician" has instances without referring to any one politician in particular.[45]
Singular and general existence are closely related to each other and some philosophers have tried to explain one as a special case of the other. For example, Frege held that general existence is more basic. One argument in favor of this position is that general existence can be expressed in terms of singular existence. For instance, the sentence "Angela Merkel exists" can be expressed as "entities exist that are identical to Angela Merkel", where the expression "being identical to Angela Merkel" is understood as a general term. A different position is defended by Quine, who gives primacy to singular existence.[46] A related question is whether there can be general existence without singular existence. According to philosophers like Henry S. Leonard, a property only has general existence if there is at least one actual object that instantiates it. A different view, defended by Nicholas Rescher, holds that properties can even exist if they have no actual instances, like the property of being a unicorn.[47]
This question has a long philosophical tradition in relation to the existence of universals. Platonists claim that universals have general existence as Platonic forms independently of the particulars that instantiate them. According to this view, the universal of redness exists independent of whether there are any red objects.[48] Aristotelianism also accepts that universals exist but holds that their existence depends on particulars that instantiate them and that they are unable to exist by themselves. According to this view, a universal that has no instances in the spacio-temporal world does not exist.[49] Nominalists claim that only particulars have existence and deny that universals exist.[50]
Concrete and abstract
Another influential distinction in ontology is between concrete and abstract objects. Many concrete objects are encountered in regular everyday life, like rocks, plants, and other people. They exist in space and time and influence each other: they have causal powers and are affected by other concrete objects. Abstract objects exist outside space and time and lack causal powers, like numbers, sets, and types.[51] The distinction between concrete and abstract objects is sometimes treated as the most general division of being.[52]
There is wide agreement that concrete objects exist but opinions are divided in regard to abstract objects. Realists accept the idea that abstract objects have independent existence.[53] Some of them claim that abstract objects have the same mode of existence as concrete objects while others maintain that they exist but in a different way.[54] Antirealists state that abstract objects do not exist, a view often combined with the idea that existence requires a location in space and time or the ability to causally interact.[55]
Fictional objects, like dragons and centaurs, are closely related to abstract objects and pose similar problems. However, the two terms are not identical. For example, the expression "the integer between two and three" refers to a fictional abstract object while the expression "integer between two and four" refers to a non-fictional abstract object. In a similar sense, there are also concrete fictional objects besides abstract fictional objects, like the winged horse of Bellerophon.[56]
Possible, contingent, and necessary
A further distinction is between merely possible, contingent, and necessary existence.[57] An entity has necessary existence if it must exist or could not fail to exist. Entities that exist but could fail to exist are contingent, while merely possible entities are entities that do not exist but could exist.[58]
Most entities encountered in ordinary experience, like telephones, sticks, and flowers, have contingent existence.[59] It is an open question whether any entities have necessary existence. According to one view, all concrete objects have contingent existence while all abstract objects have necessary existence.[60] According to some theorists, one or several necessary beings are required as the explanatory foundation of the cosmos. For instance, philosophers like Avicenna and Thomas Aquinas follow this idea and claim that God has necessary existence.[61] A few philosophers, like Baruch Spinoza, see God and the world as the same thing and hold that everything has necessary existence.[62]
There are many academic debates about whether there are merely possible objects. According to actualism, only actual entities have being. This includes both contingent and necessary entities but excludes merely possible entities.[63] This view is rejected by possibilists, who state that there are also merely possible objects besides actual objects.[64] For example, David Lewis argues that possible objects exist in the same way as actual objects. According to him, possible objects exist in possible worlds while actual objects exist in the actual world. Lewis holds that the only difference between possible worlds and the actual world is the location of the speaker: the term "actual" refers to the world of the speaker, similar to how the terms "here" and "now" refer to the spatial and temporal location of the speaker.[2]
Physical and mental
A further distinction is between entities that exist on a physical level in contrast to mental entities.[65] Physical entities include objects of regular perception, like stones, trees, and human bodies as well as entities discussed in modern physics, like electrons and protons. Physical entities can be observed and measured; they possess mass and a location in space and time.[66] Mental entities belong to the realm of the mind, like perceptions, experiences of pleasure and pain as well as beliefs, desires, and emotions. They are primarily associated with conscious experiences but also include unconscious states, like unconscious beliefs, desires, and memories.[67]
The ontological status of physical and mental entities is a frequent topic in metaphysics and philosophy of mind. According to materialists, only physical entities exist on the most fundamental level. Materialists usually explain mental entities in terms of physical processes, for example, as brain states or as patterns of neural activation. Idealists reject this view and state that mind is the ultimate foundation of existence. They hold that physical entities have a derivative form of existence, for instance, that they are mental representations or products of consciousness. Dualists, like Rene Descartes, believe that both physical and mental entities exist on the most fundamental level. They state that they are connected to one another in various ways but that one cannot be reduced to the other.[68]
Modes and degrees of existence
Closely related to the problem of different types of entities is the question of whether they differ also concerning their mode of existence. This is the case according to ontological pluralism, which states that entities belonging to different types do not just differ in their essential features but also in the way they exist.[69]
This position is sometimes found in theology. It states that God is radically different from his creation and emphasizes his uniqueness by holding that the difference affects not just God's features but also God's mode of existence.[70]
Another form of ontological pluralism distinguishes the existence of material objects from the existence of spacetime. This view holds that material objects have relative existence since they exist in spacetime. It further states that the existence of spacetime itself is not relative in this sense since it just exists without existing within another spacetime.[71]
The topic of degrees of existence is closely related to the issue of modes of existence. This topic is based on the idea that some entities exist to a higher degree or have more being than other entities, similar to how some properties have degrees, like heat and mass. According to Plato, for example, unchangeable Platonic forms have a higher degree of existence than physical objects.[72]
While the view that there are different types of entities is common in metaphysics, the idea they differ from each other concerning their modes or degrees of existence is not generally accepted.[73] For instance, philosopher Quentin Gibson maintains that a thing either exists or does not exist. This means that there is no alternative in between and that there are no degrees of existence.[74] Peter van Inwagen uses the idea that there is an intimate relation between existence and quantification to argue against different modes of existence. Quantification is related to how people count objects. Inwagen argues that if there were different modes of entities then people would need different types of numbers to count them. Since the same numbers can be used to count different types of entities, he concludes that all entities have the same mode of existence.[75]
Why anything exists at all
A central question in ontology is why anything exists at all or why there is something rather than nothing.[76] Similar questions are "why is there a world?" and "why are there individual things?". These questions focus on the idea that many things that exist are contingent, meaning they could have failed to exist. It asks whether this applies to existence as a whole as well or whether there is a reason why something exists instead of nothing.[77]
This question is different from scientific questions that seek to explain the existence of one thing, like life, in relation to the existence of another thing, like the primordial soup which may have been its origin. It is also different from most religious creation myths that explain the existence of the material world in relation to a god or gods that created it. The difference lies in the fact that these theories explain the existence of one thing in terms of the existence of another thing instead of trying to explain existence in general. The additional difficulty of the ontological question lies in the fact that one cannot refer to any other existing entity without engaging in circular reasoning.[78]
One answer to the question of why there is anything at all is called the statistical argument. It is based on the idea that besides the actual world, there are many possible worlds, which differ from the actual world in certain respects. For example, the Eiffel Tower exists in the actual world but there are possible worlds without the Eiffel Tower. There are countless variations of possible worlds but there is only one possible world that is empty, i.e., that does not contain any entities. This means that, if it was up to chance which possible world becomes actual, the chance that there is nothing is exceedingly small.[79] A closely related argument in physics explains the existence of the world as the result of random quantum fluctuations.[80]
Another response is to deny that a reason or an explanation for existence in general can be found. According to this view, existence as a whole is absurd since it is there without a reason for being there.[81]
Not all theorists accept this question as a valid or philosophically interesting question. Some philosophers, like Graham Priest and Kris McDaniel, have suggested that the term nothing refers to a global absence, which can itself be understood as a form of existence. According to this view, the answer to the question is trivial, since there is always something, even if this something is just a global absence.[82] A closely related response is to claim that an empty world is metaphysically impossible. According to this view, there is something rather than nothing because it is necessary for some things to exist.[83]
History
Western philosophy
Western philosophy originated with the Presocratic philosophers, who explored the foundational principles of all existence. Some, like Thales and Heraclitus, suggested that concrete principles, like water or fire, are the root of existence. This position was opposed by Anaximander, who held that the source must lie in an abstract principle beyond the world of human perception.[84]
Plato argued that different types of entities have different degrees of existence. He held that shadows and images exist in a weaker sense than regular material objects. He claimed that the unchangeable Platonic forms have the highest type of existence. He saw material objects as imperfect and impermanent copies of Platonic forms.[85]
While Aristotle accepted Plato's idea that forms are different from matter, he challenged the idea that forms have a higher type of existence. Instead, he held that forms cannot exist without matter[86] and claimed that different entities have different modes of existence. For example, he distinguished between substances and their accidents and between potentiality and actuality.[87]
Neoplatonists, like Plotinus, suggested that reality has a hierarchical structure. They held that a transcendent entity called "the One" or "the Good" is responsible for all existence. From it emerges the intellect, which in turn gives rise to the soul and the material world.[88]
In medieval philosophy, Anselm of Canterbury formulated the influential ontological argument. This argument aims to deduce the existence of God from the concept of God. Anselm defined God as the greatest conceivable being. He reasoned that an entity that did not exist outside his mind would not be the greatest conceivable being, leading him to the conclusion that God exists.[89]
Thomas Aquinas distinguished between the essence of a thing and its existence. According to him, the essence of a thing constitutes its fundamental nature. He argued that it is possible to understand what an object is and grasp its essence even if one does not know whether this object exists. He concluded from this observation that existence is not part of the qualities of an object and should instead be understood as a separate property.[21] Aquinas also considered the problem of creation from nothing and claimed that only God has the power to truly bring new entities into existence. These ideas later inspired Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz's theory of creation. He held that to create is to confer actual existence to possible objects.[90]
Both David Hume and Immanuel Kant rejected the idea that existence is a property. According to Hume, objects are bundles of qualities. He held that existence is not a property since there is no impression of existence besides the bundled qualities.[91] Kant came to a similar conclusion in his criticism of the ontological argument. According to him, this proof fails because one cannot deduce from the definition of a concept whether entities described by this concept exist. He held that existence does not add anything to the concept of the object, it only indicates that this concept is instantiated.[92]
Franz Brentano agreed with Kant's criticism and his claim that existence is not a real predicate. He used this idea to develop his theory of judgments, which states that all judgments are existential judgments: they either affirm or deny the existence of something. He stated that judgments like "some zebras are striped" have the logical form "there is a striped zebra" while judgments like "all zebras are striped" have the logical form "there is not a non-striped zebra".[93]
Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell aimed to refine the idea of what it means that existence is not a regular property. They distinguished between regular first-order properties of individuals and second-order properties of other properties. According to this view, to talk about existence is to talk about the second-order property of being instantiated. For instance, to deny that dinosaurs exist means that the property of being a dinosaur does not have the property of being instantiated.[94] According to Russell, the fundamental form of predication happens by applying a predicate to the proper name of an individual, as in the sentence "Laika is a dog". Russell held that talk of existence in the form of sentences like "dogs exist" is less fundamental since it means that there is an individual to which this predicate applies without naming this individual.[95]
Willard Van Orman Quine followed Frege and Russell in accepting that existence is a second-order property. He drew a close link between existence and the role of quantification in formal logic.[96] He applied this idea to scientific theories and stated that a scientific theory is committed to the existence of an entity if the theory quantifies over this entity. For example, if a theory in biology claims that "there are populations with genetic diversity" then this theory has an ontological commitment to the existence of populations with genetic diversity.[97]
Despite the influence of second-order theories, this view was not universally accepted. Alexius Meinong rejected it and claimed that existence is a property of individuals and that not all individuals have this property. This led him to the thesis that there is a difference between being and existence: all individuals have being but only some of them also exist. This implies that there are some things that do not exist, like merely possible objects and impossible objects.[98]
Eastern philosophy
Many schools of thought in Eastern philosophy discuss the problem of existence and its implications. For instance, the ancient Hindu school of Samkhya developed a metaphysical dualism which holds that there are two types of existence: pure consciousness (Purusha) and matter (Prakriti). Samkhya explains the manifestation of the universe as the interaction between these two principles.[99] A different approach was developed by Adi Shankara in his school of Advaita Vedanta. He defended a metaphysical monism by claiming that the divine (Brahman) is the ultimate reality and the only existent. According to this view, the impression that there is a universe consisting of many distinct entities is an illusion (Maya).[100] The essential features of ultimate reality are described as Sat Chit Ananda, meaning existence, consciousness, and bliss.[101]
A central doctrine in Buddhist philosophy is called the three marks of existence. The three marks are aniccā (impermanence), anattā (absence of a permanent self), and dukkha (suffering). Aniccā is the doctrine that all of existence is subject to change, meaning that everything transforms at some point and nothing lasts forever. Anattā expresses a similar state in relation to persons by claiming that people do not have a permanent identity or a separate self. Ignorance about aniccā and anattā is seen as the main cause of dukkha by leading people to form attachments that cause suffering.[102]
A central idea in many schools of Chinese philosophy, like Laozi's Daoism, is that a fundamental principle known as dao is the source of all existence. The term is often translated as "the Way" and is understood as a cosmic force that governs the natural order of the world. One position in Chinese metaphysics holds that dao is itself a form of being while another contends that it is non-being that gives rise to being.[103]
The concept of existence played a central role in Arabic-Persian philosophy. Avicenna and Al-Ghazali discussed the relation between existence and essence and held that the essence of an entity is prior to its existence. The additional step of instantiating the essence is required for the entity to come into existence. Mulla Sadra rejected this priority of essence over existence. He argued that essence is only a concept used by the mind to grasp existence. Existence, by contrast, encompasses the whole of reality, according to his view.[104]
In various disciplines
Formal logic
Formal logic studies which arguments are deductively valid.[105] First-order logic is the most commonly used system of formal logic. In it, existence is expressed using the existential quantifier ([math]\displaystyle{ \exists }[/math]). For example, the formula [math]\displaystyle{ \exists x Horse(x) }[/math] can be used to state that horses exist. The variable x ranges over all elements in the domain of quantification and the existential quantifier expresses that at least one element in this domain is a horse. In first-order logic, all singular terms, like names, refer to objects in the domain and imply that the object exists. Because of this, one can deduce that [math]\displaystyle{ \exists x Honest(x) }[/math] (someone is honest) from [math]\displaystyle{ Honest(Bill) }[/math] (Bill is honest).[106]
Many logical systems that are based on first-order logic also follow this idea. Free logic is an exception since it allows there to be empty names that do not refer to any object in the domain.[107] One motivation for this modification is that reasoning is not limited to regular objects but can also be applied to fictional objects.[108] In free logic, for instance, one can express that Pegasus is a flying horse using the formula [math]\displaystyle{ Flyinghorse(Pegasus) }[/math]. One consequence of this modification is that one cannot infer from this type of statement that something exists. This means that the inference from [math]\displaystyle{ Flyinghorse(Pegasus) }[/math] to [math]\displaystyle{ \exist x Flyinghorse(x) }[/math] is invalid in free logic even though it would be valid in first-order logic. Free logic uses an additional existence predicate ([math]\displaystyle{ E! }[/math]) to express that a singular term refers to an existing object. For example, the formula [math]\displaystyle{ E!(Homer) }[/math] can be used to express that Homer exists while the formula [math]\displaystyle{ \lnot E!(Pegasus) }[/math] states that Pegasus does not exist.[109]
Epistemology, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language
The disciplines of epistemology, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language aim to understand the nature of knowledge, mind, and language.[110] A key issue in these fields is the problem of reference, which concerns the question of how mental or linguistic representations can refer to existing objects. Examples of such representations are beliefs, thoughts, perceptions, words, and sentences. For instance, in the sentence "Barack Obama is a Democrat", the name "Barack Obama" refers to a particular individual. In relation to perception, the problem of reference concerns the question of whether or to what extent perceptual impressions bring the perceiver in contact with reality by presenting existing objects rather than illusions.[111]
Closely related to the problem of reference is the relation between true representations and existence. According to truthmaker theory, true representations require a truthmaker, i.e., an entity whose existence is responsible for the fact that the representation is true. For example, the sentence "kangaroos live in Australia" is true because there are kangaroos in Australia: the existence of these kangaroos is the truthmaker of the sentence. Truthmaker theory states that there is a close relation between truth and existence: there exists a truthmaker for every true representation.[112]
Existentialism
Existentialism is a school of thought that explores the nature of human existence. One of its key ideas is that existence precedes essence, a claim which expresses the notion that existence is more basic than essence and that the nature and purpose of human beings are not pregiven but develop in the process of living. According to this view, humans are thrown into a world that lacks preexistent intrinsic meaning. They have to determine for themselves what their purpose is and what meaning their life should have. Existentialists use this idea to focus on the role of freedom and responsibility in actively shaping one's life.[113]
See also
References
Notes
- ↑ In his own terminology, Heidegger reserves the terms "Existenz" and "Ek-sistenz" to characterize the mode of being of Dasein, which is the mode of being characteristic of human beings.[19]
Citations
- ↑
- ↑ 2.0 2.1 2.2 Lowe 2005, existence.
- ↑
- ↑
- Harper 2017
- Hoad 1993, p. 160
- ↑
- Lowe 2005, existence
- Sorensen 2023, lead section
- Vallicella 2010, p. xi
- ↑
- ↑
- Prior 2006, p. 493, Existences
- Van Inwagen 2023
- Nelson 2022, lead section, §2. Meinongianism
- ↑
- Van Inwagen 2023
- Nelson 2022, lead section, §2. Meinongianism
- Shand 2004, p. 49
- ↑
- Divers 2011, pp. 570–574
- Yagisawa 2011, pp. 270–272
- ↑ Chakrabarti 2013, pp. 106–107.
- ↑
- ↑
- Dobrez 2014, p. 109
- Heisig, Kasulis & Maraldo 2011, p. 830
- Leclerc 2002, p. 49
- Sorensen 2023, lead section
- ↑
- Gibson 1998, p. 2
- Ceylan 1993, pp. 329–337
- Nelson 2022, lead section
- Platter 2021, p. 28
- ↑
- Gibson 1998, pp. 1–2
- Vallicella 2010, p. 16
- Balthasar 2000, p. 82
- Shand 2004, pp. 47–48
- ↑
- Robinson 2008, p. 139, 7. Can We Make Sense of the Idea that God's Existence is Identical to His Essence?
- Novotný & Novák 2014, pp. 46–47
- Berto 2012, pp. 31–32
- Bottani & Davies 2013, p. 126
- ↑
- Robinson 2008, p. 139, 7. Can We Make Sense of the Idea that God's Existence is Identical to His Essence?
- Novotný & Novák 2014, pp. 46–47
- Berto 2012, pp. 31–32
- ↑
- Nicholson 1996, pp. 357–374
- Wheeler 2020, §2.2.1 The Question
- Vallicella 2010, p. 1
- ↑
- Nicholson 1996, pp. 357–358
- Wheeler 2020, §2.2.1 The Question
- Boyle 2017, p. 133
- Inwood 1999, pp. 89–100
- ↑
- Reck 2000, pp. 155–156
- Aho 2021, pp. 268–270
- Inwood 1999, p. 60
- ↑ 20.0 20.1 20.2 Casati & Fujikawa, §2a. Meinongianism.
- ↑ 21.0 21.1 Nelson 2022, lead section.
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, lead section
- Penelope 1998, lead section
- Casati & Fujikawa, lead section
- Blackburn 2008, existence
- ↑
- Penelope 1998, §1 Objects and existence
- Penelope 1998, §1 Objects and existence
- Nelson 2022, lead section
- Nelson 2022, 1. Frege and Russell: Existence is not a Property of Individuals
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, lead section, §1. Existence as a Second-Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification
- Blackburn 2008, existence
- ↑ 25.0 25.1
- Blackburn 2008, existence
- Casati & Fujikawa, §1. Existence as a Second-Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, §1. Existence as a Second-Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification
- Lowe 2005, existence
- ↑ Nelson 2022, §1. Frege and Russell: Existence is not a Property of Individuals.
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, lead section, §1. Existence as a Second-Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification
- Penelope 1998, §2 The quantifier account of existence
- Blackburn 2008, existence
- Lowe 2005, existence
- ↑ Fierro 2012, p. 37.
- ↑ Penelope 1998, §2 The quantifier account of existence.
- ↑
- Penelope 1998, §2 The quantifier account of existence
- Blackburn 2008, existence
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, 1. Frege and Russell: Existence is not a Property of Individuals
- Penelope 1998, §2 The quantifier account of existence
- Nelson 2022, 1. Frege and Russell: Existence is not a Property of Individuals
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, lead section, §2. Existence as a First-Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification
- Nelson 2022, lead section
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, §2a. Meinongianism
- Lowe 2005, existence
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, 2. Meinongianism
- Casati & Fujikawa, §2a. Meinongianism
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, §2a. Meinongianism
- Lowe 2005, existence
- Tymieniecka 2012, p. 208
- ↑ 37.0 37.1 37.2 Penelope 1998, §1 Objects and existence.
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, 2. Meinongianism
- Penelope 1998, §1 Objects and existence
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, 2. Meinongianism
- Casati & Fujikawa, §2a. Meinongianism
- Casati & Fujikawa, §2a. Meinongianism
- Jacquette 2015, pp. 78–79, 180
- ↑ 40.0 40.1 Casati & Fujikawa, §2b. Universalism.
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, 3. An Anti-Meinongian First-Order View
- Casati & Fujikawa, §2b. Universalism
- ↑ Nelson 2022, 3. An Anti-Meinongian First-Order View.
- ↑
- Van Inwagen 2023
- Hofweber 2023, 3.1 Different conceptions of ontology
- Livingston & Cutrofello 2015, pp. 63–64
- Gibson 1998, pp. 3–4
- Nelson 2022, 3. An Anti-Meinongian First-Order View
- ↑
- Van Inwagen 2023
- Prior 2006, p. 493, Existences
- Gibson 1998, pp. 3–4
- Nelson 2022, 3. An Anti-Meinongian First-Order View
- ↑
- Lambert 1994, pp. 3–4
- Rescher 1957, pp. 65–69
- Hailperin 1967, p. 251
- Shand 2004, pp. 52–53
- ↑ Lambert 1994, pp. 3–4.
- ↑
- Rescher 1957, pp. 65–69
- Hailperin 1967, p. 251
- ↑
- Gibson 1998, pp. 133–134
- Balaguer 2016, 1. What is Platonism?
- ↑ Gibson 1998, p. 138.
- ↑ Gibson 1998, pp. 3–4, 137.
- ↑
- Penelope 1998, lead section
- Falguera, Martínez-Vidal & Rosen 2022, lead section, §1. Introduction
- Stadler & Stöltzner 2013, pp. 89–91
- Prior 2006, pp. 498–499, Existences
- ↑ Honderich 2005, Ontology.
- ↑
- Belfiore 2016, p. 110
- Faulkner & Gregersen 2017, p. 298
- Prior 2006, pp. 498–499, Existences
- ↑
- Van Inwagen 2023
- Prior 2006, pp. 493, 498–499, Existences
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, §2a. Meinongianism
- Plebani 2013, p. 5
- ↑ Prior 2006, p. 493, Existences.
- ↑
- Penelope 1998, lead section
- Gibson 1998, pp. 157–8
- Shand 2004, pp. 49, 52
- ↑
- Gibson 1998, pp. 157–8
- Albertazzi & Jacquette 2017, p. 87
- Pruss & Rasmussen 2018, pp. 1–2
- Shand 2004, p. 52
- ↑ Pruss & Rasmussen 2018, pp. 1–2.
- ↑ Pruss & Rasmussen 2018, pp. 1–4.
- ↑
- Gibson 1998, pp. 157–8
- Pruss & Rasmussen 2018, pp. 1–6
- Haan 2020, p. 381
- Turner 2004, p. 238
- ↑
- Lin 2018, p. 152
- Nadler 2023, § 2.1 God or Nature
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, §3. An Anti-Meinongian First-Order View
- Shand 2004, pp. 49–50
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, §2. Meinongianism
- Shand 2004, pp. 49–50
- ↑ Penelope 1998, lead section.
- ↑
- Smart 2023, lead section, §Types of materialist theory
- Markosian 2009, pp. 486–487, Physical object
- ↑
- ↑
- Kelly 2004, pp. 87–88
- Goldschmidt & Pearce 2017, p. ix
- Darvill 2009, idealism
- Smart 2023, lead section, §Types of materialist theory
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, lead section, §3. How Many Ways of Being Existent?
- McDaniel 2017, p. 77
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, lead section, §3. How Many Ways of Being Existent?
- McDaniel 2017, pp. 5–6
- ↑ Casati & Fujikawa, §3. How Many Ways of Being Existent?.
- ↑
- Poidevin et al. 2009, pp. 227–228
- Van Inwagen 2023
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, §3. How Many Ways of Being Existent?
- Gibson 1998, pp. 5–8
- ↑ Gibson 1998, pp. 5–8.
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, §3. How Many Ways of Being Existent?
- Berto & Plebani 2015, p. 60
- ↑
- Lowe 2005, existence
- Casati & Fujikawa, lead section, §4. Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing?
- Van Inwagen 2009, pp. 109–112
- Morin 2017, p. 46
- Sorensen 2023, lead section, §1. Why is there something rather than nothing?
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, §4. Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing?
- Van Inwagen 2009, pp. 109–112
- Morin 2017, p. 46
- Sorensen 2023, lead section, §1. Why is there something rather than nothing?
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, §4. Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing?
- Van Inwagen 2009, pp. 109–112
- Morin 2017, p. 46
- Sorensen 2023, lead section, §1. Why is there something rather than nothing?
- Søvik 2022, p. 482
- ↑
- Casati & Fujikawa, §4. Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing?
- Sorensen 2023, lead section, §1. Why is there something rather than nothing?
- ↑ He, Gao & Cai 2014, p. 083510-1.
- ↑
- ↑ Casati & Fujikawa, §4. Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing?.
- ↑ Pruss & Rasmussen 2018, pp. 4–5.
- ↑
- Graham, lead section, §1a. The Milesians, §1d. Heraclitus
- Duignan 2010, pp. 9–11
- ↑
- Van Inwagen 2023
- Poidevin et al. 2009, pp. 227–228
- ↑
- Trott 2019, pp. 109–110
- Grayling 2019, Aristotle
- ↑
- Poidevin et al. 2009, pp. 228–229
- Menn 2021, §1. The senses of being and the necessity of Δ. 7
- ↑
- Graham, 6. Post-Hellenistic Thought
- Adamson 2015, pp. 209–215
- Furley 2005, pp. 357–388
- Camus 2007, p. 45
- Lawson 2004, p. 200
- ↑
- Grayling 2019, Anselm
- Dehsen 2013, p. 10
- Prior 2006, pp. 493–494, Existences
- ↑ Prior 2006, p. 494, Existences.
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, lead section
- Prior 2006, p. 495, Existences
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, lead section
- Casati & Fujikawa, §1. Existence as a Second-Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification
- ↑
- Kriegel 2018, pp. 103–104, 119
- Brandl & Textor 2022, lead section, §1.3 Part III: Existential Judgements, §2. Brentano and His Precursors on Existential Judgement
- Rollinger 2013, p. 226
- Husserl 2019, p. 184
- Prior 2006, pp. 495–496, Existences
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, lead section
- Blackburn 2008, existence
- ↑ Prior 2006, pp. 496–498, Existences.
- ↑
- Lowe 2005, existence
- Casati & Fujikawa, §2a. Meinongianism
- ↑ Casati & Fujikawa, §1. Existence as a Second-Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification, §2a. Meinongianism.
- ↑
- Nelson 2022, lead section
- Casati & Fujikawa, §2a. Meinongianism
- ↑
- Leaman 2002, pp. 77–78
- Perrett 2016, The classical period of Indian philosophy
- Ruzsa 2023, lead section, §4. Metaphysics
- ↑
- Perrett 2016, The medieval period of Indian philosophy
- Dalal 2021, lead section, 1. Life and Works
- Menon, lead section
- Leaman 2002, pp. 77–78
- ↑
- Vanamali 2015, pp. 53–54
- Mahapatra 2020, p. 110
- ↑
- ↑
- Perkins 2019, lead section, §3.1 Monism
- EB staff 2017, Periods of development of Chinese philosophy
- Wang, Bao & Guan 2020, pp. 6–8
- Csikszentmihalyi & Ivanhoe 1999, p. 35
- ↑
- Leaman 2002, pp. 77–78
- DeGrood 1976, p. 37
- ↑
- MacFarlane 2017
- Corkum 2015, pp. 753–767
- Blair & Johnson 2000, pp. 93–95
- Magnus 2005, pp. 12–14, 1.6 Formal languages
- ↑
- Shapiro & Kouri Kissel 2022, §2.1 Building blocks
- Cook 2009, p. 111
- Kind 2018, p. 236
- Casati & Fujikawa, lead section, §1. Existence as a Second-Order Property and Its Relation to Quantification
- ↑ Nolt 2021, lead section, §1. The Basics.
- ↑ Nolt 2021, §5.4 Logics of Fiction.
- ↑
- Morscher & Hieke 2013, p. 118
- Nolt 2021, lead section, §1. The Basics, §5.4 Logics of Fiction
- Sider 2010, p. 129
- ↑
- Martinich & Stroll 2023, lead section, The nature of epistemology
- Audi 2006, §Epistemology, §Philosophy of mind, §Philosophy of language
- ↑
- Urban 2014, p. 33
- Raftopoulos & Machamer 2012, pp. 1–2, 142
- Michaelson & Reimer 2022, lead section, §1. Introduction
- ↑
- Asay, lead section
- Smith, Mulligan & Simons 2013, pp. 9–10
- ↑
- Burnham & Papandreopoulos, lead section, §1c. Freedom, §1e. Existence, §1f. Irrationality/Absurdity
- Aho 2023, lead section
Sources
- Adamson, Peter (2015) (in en). Philosophy in the Hellenistic and Roman Worlds. A History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps. 2. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-872802-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=J5_oCQAAQBAJ. Retrieved 2023-05-25.
- Addis, Laird (2 May 2013) (in en). Mind: Ontology and Explanation: Collected Papers 1981-2005. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-032715-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=Vk6ZEN6vByUC&pg=PA49.
- "The American Heritage Dictionary entry: existence". HarperCollins. 2022. https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=existence&submit.x=58&submit.y=14.
- Aho, Kevin (2021). "Ek-sistence (Ek-sistenz)". The Cambridge Heidegger Lexicon. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-00274-6. https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/abs/cambridge-heidegger-lexicon/eksistence-eksistenz/C78548237FFDBE1D518259C7DFA0BC9C.
- Aho, Kevin (2023). "Existentialism". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/existentialism/.
- Albertazzi, Liliana; Jacquette, Dale (5 July 2017) (in en). The School of Alexius Meinong. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-351-88226-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=wkQrDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA87.
- Asay, Jamin. "Truthmaker Theory". https://iep.utm.edu/truth-ma/.
- Audi, Robert (2006). "Philosophy". in Borchert, Donald M.. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 7: Oakeshott - Presupposition (2. ed.). Thomson Gale, Macmillan Reference. ISBN 978-0-02-865787-5. https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/philosophy.
- Balaguer, Mark (2016). "Platonism in Metaphysics". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 1. What is Platonism?. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/platonism/#1.
- Balthasar, Hans Urs von (1 January 2000) (in en). Theo-Logic, Vol. 1: Truth of the World. Ignatius Press. ISBN 978-0-89870-718-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=AlRLAgAAQBAJ&pg=PT82.
- Belfiore, Francesco (17 November 2016) (in en). The Triadic Structure of the Mind: Outlines of a Philosophical System. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7618-6857-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=IQp5DQAAQBAJ&pg=PA110.
- Berto, Francesco (17 October 2012) (in en). Existence as a Real Property: The Ontology of Meinongianism. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-007-4206-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=oMN1Si2wPVIC&pg=PA31.
- Berto, Francesco; Plebani, Matteo (29 January 2015) (in en). Ontology and Metaontology: A Contemporary Guide. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4725-7330-8. https://books.google.com/books?id=Jy3bBQAAQBAJ&pg=PA60.
- Blackburn, Simon (1 January 2008). "existence" (in en). The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954143-0. https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/oi/authority.20110803095804522;jsessionid=AEB41DBFF0B3EBCDCCB8A1E0DAFD4EB0.
- Blair, J. Anthony; Johnson, Ralph H. (2000). "Informal Logic: An Overview". Informal Logic 20 (2). doi:10.22329/il.v20i2.2262. https://philpapers.org/rec/BLAILA-3. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
- Bottani, Andrea; Davies, Richard (2 May 2013) (in en). Modes of Existence: Papers in Ontology and Philosophical Logic. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-032753-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=15LIl3X8SnUC&pg=PA126.
- Boyle, Kirk (15 November 2017). "'The Missing Element is the Human Element': Ontological Difference and teh World-Ecological Crisis of the Capitalocene" (in en). Eco Culture: Disaster, Narrative, Discourse. Lexington Books. ISBN 978-1-4985-3477-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=GqhFDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA133.
- Brandl, Johannes L.; Textor, Mark (2022). "Brentano's Theory of Judgement". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/brentano-judgement/.
- Burnham, Douglas; Papandreopoulos, George. "Existentialism". https://iep.utm.edu/existent/.
- Camus, Albert (2007) (in en). Christian Metaphysics and Neoplatonism. University of Missouri Press. ISBN 978-0-8262-6622-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=e_myYMkRuN4C. Retrieved 2023-05-28.
- Casati, Filippo; Fujikawa, Naoya. "Existence". https://iep.utm.edu/existenc/.
- Ceylan, Yasin (1993). "A Critical Approach to the Avicennian Distinction of Essence and Existence". Islamic Studies 32 (3): 329–337. ISSN 0578-8072. https://www.jstor.org/stable/20840134.
- Chakrabarti, A. (14 March 2013) (in en). Denying Existence: The Logic, Epistemology and Pragmatics of Negative Existentials and Fictional Discourse. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-017-1223-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=bLStBgAAQBAJ&pg=PT106.
- Coakley, Sarah; Shelemay, Kay Kaufman (2007) (in en). Pain and Its Transformations: The Interface of Biology and Culture. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-02456-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=sQULdfIlBIYC&pg=PA110.
- Cook, Roy T. (20 March 2009) (in en). Dictionary of Philosophical Logic. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-0-7486-3197-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=JfaqBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA111.
- Corkum, Philip (2015). "Generality and Logical Constancy". Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 71 (4): 753–768. doi:10.17990/rpf/2015_71_4_0753. ISSN 0870-5283.
- Cornwell, Neil (19 July 2013) (in en). The absurd in literature. Manchester University Press. ISBN 978-1-84779-657-8. https://books.google.com/books?id=X2S5DwAAQBAJ&pg=PT16.
- Csikszentmihalyi, Mark; Ivanhoe, Philip J. (1 January 1999) (in en). Religious and Philosophical Aspects of the Laozi. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-4111-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=ssS4tFD-CvwC&pg=PA35.
- "existence". Cambridge University Press. https://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/english/existence.
- Dalal, Neil (2021). "Śaṅkara". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/shankara/.
- Darvill, Timothy (1 January 2009). "idealism" (in en). The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Archaeology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-953404-3. https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/acref/9780199534043.001.0001/acref-9780199534043-e-1926.
- DeGrood, David H. (1 January 1976) (in en). Philosophies of Essence: An Examination of the Category of Essence. John Benjamins Publishing. ISBN 978-90-6032-076-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=3vYOp1AGpVUC&pg=PA37.
- Dehsen, Christian von (13 September 2013) (in en). Philosophers and Religious Leaders. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-95102-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=cU7cAAAAQBAJ. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
- Divers, J. (2011). "Worlds and Individuals, Possible and Otherwise, by Takashi Yagisawa". Mind 120 (478): 570–574. doi:10.1093/mind/fzr027. https://philpapers.org/rec/DIVWAI.
- Dobrez, L. A. C. (13 January 2014) (in en). The Existential and its Exits: Literary and Philosophical Perspectives on the Works of Beckett, Ionesco, Genet and Pinter. A&C Black. ISBN 978-1-4725-1467-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=h8FMAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA109.
- Duignan, Brian, ed (15 August 2010) (in en). Ancient Philosophy: From 600 BCE to 500 CE. The Rosen Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN 978-1-61530-141-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=MfBS-RXJ5RsC. Retrieved 28 May 2023.
- "Chinese philosophy" (in en). 2017. https://www.britannica.com/topic/Chinese-philosophy.
- "Mind" (in en). 3 July 2023. https://www.britannica.com/topic/mind.
- Falguera, José L.; Martínez-Vidal, Concha; Rosen, Gideon (2022). "Abstract Objects". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. lead section, §1. Introduction. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/abstract-objects/.
- Faulkner, Nicholas; Gregersen, Erik (15 December 2017) (in en). The History of Mathematics. The Rosen Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN 978-1-68048-777-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=5-JhDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA298.
- Fierro, Ricardo D. (13 January 2012) (in en). Mathematics for Elementary School Teachers. Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-1-133-71210-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=MTM9AAAAQBAJ&pg=PA37.
- II. From Aristotle to Augustine. Routledge History of Philosophy. Routledge. 2005. ISBN 978-0-203-02845-2.
- Gibson, Q. B. (31 July 1998) (in en). The Existence Principle. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-0-7923-5188-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=0BvTfX-swZ0C.
- Goldschmidt, Tyron; Pearce, Kenneth L. (1 December 2017) (in en). Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-106399-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=QgJCDwAAQBAJ&pg=PR9.
- Graham, Jacob N.. "Ancient Greek Philosophy". https://iep.utm.edu/ancient-greek-philosophy/.
- Grayling, A. C. (20 June 2019) (in en). The History of Philosophy. Penguin UK. ISBN 978-0-241-98086-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=bDJwDwAAQBAJ. Retrieved 24 May 2023.
- Haan, Daniel D. De (10 August 2020) (in en). Necessary Existence and the Doctrine of Being in Avicenna's Metaphysics of the Healing. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-43452-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=XV75DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA381.
- Hailperin, Theodore (August 1967). "Nicholas Rescher. Definitions of "existence." Philosophical studies (Minneapolis), vol. 8 (1957), pp. 65–69. - Karel Lambert. Notes on "E!". Philosophical studies (Minneapolis), vol. 9 (1958), pp. 60–63.". Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2). doi:10.2307/2271672.
- Harper, Douglas (2017). "existence" (in en). https://www.etymonline.com/word/existence.
- He, Dongshan; Gao, Dongfeng; Cai, Qing-yu (3 April 2014). "Spontaneous creation of the universe from nothing". Physical Review D 89 (8): 083510. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.89.083510. Bibcode: 2014PhRvD..89h3510H.
- Heisig, James W.; Kasulis, Thomas P.; Maraldo, John C. (31 July 2011) (in en). Japanese Philosophy: A Sourcebook. University of Hawaii Press. ISBN 978-0-8248-3707-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=GVgEEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA830.
- Hoad, T. F. (1993). The concise Oxford dictionary of english etymology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-283098-2.
- Hofweber, Thomas (2023). "Logic and Ontology". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-ontology/#Onto.
- Honderich, Ted, ed (2005). "Ontology". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. https://philpapers.org/rec/HONTOC-2. Retrieved 2 January 2022.
- Husserl, Edmund (1 October 2019) (in en). Logic and General Theory of Science. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-3-030-14529-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=ikqzDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA184.
- Inwood, Michael (1999). A Heidegger Dictionary. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-631-19094-3.
- Jacquette, Dale (2015). Alexius Meinong, The Shepherd of Non-Being. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-18074-8. https://books.google.com/books?id=7jswCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA78.
- Kelly, Eugene (30 March 2004) (in en). The Basics of Western Philosophy. Greenwood Publishing Group. ISBN 978-0-313-32352-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=AFwr3CCoqAEC&pg=PA87.
- Kim, Jaegwon (2006). "1. Introduction". Philosophy of Mind (2nd ed.). Boulder: Westview Press. ISBN 978-0-8133-4458-4. https://philpapers.org/rec/KIMPOM-3. Retrieved 2021-06-01.
- Kind, Amy (6 July 2018) (in en). Philosophy of Mind in the Twentieth and Twenty-First Centuries: The History of the Philosophy of Mind, Volume 6. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-429-01938-8. https://books.google.com/books?id=oDhjDwAAQBAJ&pg=PT236.
- Kriegel, Uriah (13 February 2018) (in en). Brentano's Philosophical System: Mind, Being, Value. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-250910-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=Yz5MDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA119.
- Lambert, Karel (1 January 1994). "A Note on Singular and General Existence". KRITERION – Journal of Philosophy 7 (1): 3–4. doi:10.1515/krt-1994-010704.
- Lawson, Russell M. (2004) (in en). Science in the Ancient World: An Encyclopedia. ABC-CLIO. ISBN 978-1-85109-534-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=1AY1ALzh9V0C. Retrieved 2023-05-28.
- Leaman, Oliver (11 September 2002) (in en). Key Concepts in Eastern Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-68905-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=_4crBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA77.
- Leclerc, Ivor (2002) (in en). The Nature of Physical Existence. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-29561-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=_B2KaiGu038C&pg=PA49.
- Lin, Martin (2018). "The Principle of Sufficient Reason in Spinoza". in Rocca, Michael Della (in en). The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-533582-8. https://books.google.com/books?id=OWIwDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA152.
- Liu, Jeeloo; Berger, Douglas (13 June 2014) (in en). Nothingness in Asian Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-68383-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=p5nOAwAAQBAJ&pg=PT150.
- Livingston, Paul; Cutrofello, Andrew (8 December 2015) (in en). The Problems of Contemporary Philosophy: A Critical Guide for the Unaffiliated. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-5095-0144-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=yztcCwAAQBAJ&pg=PT63.
- Lowe, E. J. (1 January 2005). "existence" (in en). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/acref/9780199264797.001.0001/acref-9780199264797-e-828.
- MacFarlane, John (2017). "Logical Constants". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logical-constants/#SynTer.
- Magnus, P. D. (2005). Forall X: An Introduction to Formal Logic. Victoria, BC, Canada: State University of New York Oer Services. ISBN 978-1-64176-026-3. https://philpapers.org/rec/MAGFXI. Retrieved 29 December 2021.
- Mahapatra, Debidatta Aurobinda (14 May 2020) (in en). The Philosophy of Sri Aurobindo: Indian Philosophy and Yoga in the Contemporary World. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-350-12487-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=tRveDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA110.
- Markosian, Ned (13 April 2009). "Physical object". in Kim, Jaekwon; Sosa, Ernest; Rosenkrantz, Gary S. (in en). A Companion to Metaphysics. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-4051-5298-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=lQ2xDwAAQBAJ.
- Martinich, A.P.; Stroll, Avrum (2023). "Epistemology". https://www.britannica.com/topic/epistemology.
- McDaniel, Kris (28 July 2017) (in en). The Fragmentation of Being. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-103037-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=8F0vDwAAQBAJ&pg=PT89.
- Menn, Stephen (2021). "Aristotle On The Many Senses Of Being". in Caston, Victor. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Volume 59 Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Volume 59. OUP. ISBN 978-0-19-189162-5.
- Menon, Sangeetha. "Vedanta, Advaita". https://iep.utm.edu/advaita-vedanta/.
- Michaelson, Eliot; Reimer, Marga (2022). "Reference". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reference/.
- Morin, Marie-Eve (23 June 2017) (in en). Continental Realism and Its Discontents. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-1-4744-2115-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=8HkxEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA46.
- Morscher, E.; Hieke, A. (14 March 2013) (in en). New Essays in Free Logic: In Honour of Karel Lambert. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-015-9761-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=zn3oCAAAQBAJ&pg=PA118.
- "Definition of EXISTENCE" (in en). 3 August 2023. https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/existence.
- Nadler, Steven (2023). "Baruch Spinoza". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/spinoza/.
- Nelson, Michael (2022). "Existence". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/existence/.
- Nicholson, Graeme (1996). "The Ontological Difference". American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (4): 357–374. ISSN 0003-0481. https://www.jstor.org/stable/20009875.
- Nolt, John (2021). "Free Logic". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-free/.
- Novotný, Daniel D.; Novák, Lukáš (16 April 2014) (in en). Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives in Metaphysics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-63009-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=2QBgAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA46.
- Penelope, Mackie (1998). "Existence" (in en). Routledge. https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/existence/v-1.
- Perkins, Franklin (2019). "Metaphysics in Chinese Philosophy". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/chinese-metaphysics/.
- Perrett, Roy W. (4 February 2016) (in en). An Introduction to Indian Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-85356-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=q7wwCwAAQBAJ. Retrieved 9 June 2023.
- Platter, Jonathan M. (5 July 2021) (in en). Divine Simplicity and the Triune Identity: A Critical Dialogue with the Theological Metaphysics of Robert W. Jenson. Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. ISBN 978-3-11-073601-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=U148EAAAQBAJ&pg=PT28.
- Plebani, Matteo (2 May 2013). "Introduction" (in en). Existence and Nature: New Perspectives. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-032180-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=pkNb_3NYyz0C&pg=PA5.
- Poidevin, Robin Le; Peter, Simons; Andrew, McGonigal; Cameron, Ross P. (2 April 2009) (in en). The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-15585-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=EVh8AgAAQBAJ&pg=PT290.
- Prior, A. N. (2006). "Existences". in Borchert, Donald. Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy Volume 3 (2nd ed.). Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-865790-5. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO.
- Pruss, Alexander R.; Rasmussen, Joshua L. (2018) (in en). Necessary Existence. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-874689-8. https://books.google.com/books?id=2SJLDwAAQBAJ.
- Raftopoulos, Athanassios; Machamer, Peter (12 April 2012) (in en). Perception, Realism, and the Problem of Reference. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-19877-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=80ZitZBNao4C&pg=PA1.
- Reck, Johann Georg (2000). "Ek-sistenz". Wörterbuch der Psychotherapie. Springer. pp. 155–156. doi:10.1007/978-3-211-99131-2_412. ISBN 978-3-211-99130-5.
- Reicher, Maria (2022). "Nonexistent Objects". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. lead section, §1. The Concept of a Nonexistent Object. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nonexistent-objects/.
- Rescher, Nicholas (October 1957). "Definitions of "existence"". Philosophical Studies 8 (5): 65–69. doi:10.1007/bf02304902.
- Robinson, Howard (2008). "7. Can We Make Sense of the Idea that God's Existence is Identical to His Essence?". in Stone, Martin William Francis. Reason, faith and history: philosophical essays for Paul Helm. Ashgate Publishing. ISBN 978-0-7546-0926-1.
- Rollinger, Robin D. (29 June 2013) (in en). Husserl's Position in the School of Brentano. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-017-1808-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=6FJFBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA226.
- Ruzsa, Ferenc (2023). "Sankhya". https://iep.utm.edu/sankhya/.
- Searle, John R. (1 November 2004) (in en). Mind: A Brief Introduction. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-988268-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=5G_iBwAAQBAJ&pg=PT183.
- Shand, John (1 March 2004) (in en). Fundamentals of Philosophy. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-58831-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=uoCh8mpbZO4C&pg=PA47.
- Shapiro, Stewart; Kouri Kissel, Teresa (2022). "Classical Logic". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-classical/.
- Sider, Theodore (7 January 2010) (in en). Logic for Philosophy. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-265881-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=GK8SEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA129.
- Smart, John Jamieson Carswell (28 July 2023). "Materialism" (in en). https://www.britannica.com/topic/materialism-philosophy.
- Smith, Barry; Mulligan, Kevin; Simons, Peter (2 May 2013). Monnoyer, Jean-Maurice. ed (in en). Metaphysics and Truthmakers. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-032691-8. https://books.google.com/books?id=RNg2n2yVrCUC&pg=PA9.
- Smith, Peter; Worden, David (2003) (in en). Key Beliefs, Ultimate Questions and Life Issues. Heinemann. ISBN 978-0-435-30699-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=8emELTpHWSEC&pg=PA18.
- Sorensen, Roy (2023). "Nothingness". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nothingness/.
- Søvik, Atle Ottesen (4 April 2022) (in en). A Basic Theory of Everything: A Fundamental Theoretical Framework for Science and Philosophy. Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. ISBN 978-3-11-077095-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=a4dnEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA482.
- Stadler, Friedrich; Stöltzner, Michael (2 May 2013) (in en). Time and History: Proceedings of the 28. International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium, Kirchberg am Wechsel, Austria 2005. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-033321-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=ftrmBQAAQBAJ&pg=PA89.
- Trott, Adriel M. (8 October 2019) (in en). Aristotle on the Matter of Form: I Feminist Metaphysics of Generation. Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-1-4744-5525-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=SHsxEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA109.
- Turner, Denys (16 September 2004) (in en). Faith, Reason and the Existence of God. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-60256-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=Dik3_ZjWo-MC&pg=PA238.
- Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa (6 December 2012) (in en). The Later Husserl and the Idea of Phenomenology: Idealism-Realism, Historicity and Nature Papers and Debate of the International Phenomenological Conference Held at the University of Waterloo, Canada, April 9–14, 1969. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-010-2882-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=mprnCAAAQBAJ&pg=PA208.
- Urban, Wilbur Marshall (3 June 2014) (in en). Language and Reality: The Philosophy of Language and the Principles of Symbolism. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-85195-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=xLS3AwAAQBAJ&pg=PT33.
- Vallicella, William F. (2010). A Paradigm theory of existence: Onto-Theology vindicated. Kluwer Academic. ISBN 978-90-481-6128-7.
- Van Inwagen, Peter (2009). Metaphysics (3. ed.). Westview Press. ISBN 978-0-8133-4356-3.
- Van Inwagen, Peter (2023). "Existence" (in en). https://www.britannica.com/topic/existence.
- Vanamali (30 January 2015) (in en). The Science of the Rishis: The Spiritual and Material Discoveries of the Ancient Sages of India. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-1-62055-387-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=QGAoDwAAQBAJ&pg=PT53.
- Wang, Yueqing; Bao, Qinggang; Guan, Guoxing (16 March 2020) (in en). History of Chinese Philosophy Through Its Key Terms. Springer Nature. ISBN 978-981-15-2572-8. https://books.google.com/books?id=gSfXDwAAQBAJ. Retrieved 13 June 2023.
- Wheeler, Michael (2020). "Martin Heidegger". Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/heidegger/.
- Yagisawa, Takashi (2011). "Précis of Worlds and Individuals, Possible and Otherwise". Analytic Philosophy 52 (4): 270–272. doi:10.1111/j.2153-960X.2011.00534.x. https://philpapers.org/rec/YAGPOW.
Further reading
- Aristotle (1998). The Metaphysics. Penguin Books. ISBN 978-0-14-044619-7.
- Thalheimer, Alvin (1920) (in en). The Meaning of the Terms: 'existence' and 'reality'. Princeton University Press. OCLC 7940545. https://books.google.com/books?id=JCWqKvkMy7IC.
- Williams, Christopher John Fardo (1981) (in en). What is Existence?. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824429-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=i9XEwAEACAAJ.
- W. Kneale; G. E. Moore (July 15, 1936). Symposium: Is Existence a Predicate?. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume. 15. Oxford University Press. pp. 154–188. doi:10.1093/aristoteliansupp/15.1.154.
External links
Original source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Existence.
Read more |